Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Rape as an essentially contested concept.Eric Reitan - 2001 - Hypatia 16 (2):43-66.
    : Because "rape" has such a powerful appraisive meaning, how one defines the term has normative significance. Those who define rape rigidly so as to exclude contemporary feminist understandings are therefore seeking to silence some moral perspectives "by definition." I argue that understanding rape as an essentially contested concept allows the concept sufficient flexibility to permit open moral discourse, while at the same time preserving a core meaning that can frame the discourse.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Rape as an Essentially Contested Concept.Eric Reitan - 2001 - Hypatia 16 (2):43-66.
    Because “rape” has such a powerful appraisive meaning, how one defines the term has normative significance. Those who define rape rigidly so as to exclude contemporary feminist understandings are therefore seeking to silence some moral perspectives “by definition.” I argue that understanding rape as an essentially contested concept allows the concept sufficient flexibility to permit open moral discourse, while at the same time preserving a core meaning that can frame the discourse.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Communicative punishment and the role of the victim.R. A. Duff & S. E. Marshall - 2004 - Criminal Justice Ethics 23 (2):39-50.
  • The epistemological significance of psychic trauma.Karyn L. Freedman - 2006 - Hypatia 21 (2):104-125.
    This essay explores the epistemological significance of the kinds of beliefs that grow out of traumatic experiences, such as the rape survivor's belief that she is never safe. On current theories of justification, beliefs like this one are generally dismissed due to either insufficient evidence or insufficient propositional content. Here, Freedman distinguishes two discrete sides of the aftermath of psychic trauma, the shattered self and the shattered worldview. This move enables us to see these beliefs as beliefs; in other words, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Rethinking the presumption of atheism.Keith Burgess-Jackson - 2018 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 84 (1):93-111.
    Is there—or rather, ought there to be—a presumption of atheism, as Antony Flew so famously argued nearly half a century ago? It is time to revisit this issue. After clarifying the concept of a presumption of atheism, I take up the evaluative question of whether there ought to be a presumption of atheism, focusing on Flew’s arguments for an affirmative answer. I conclude that Flew’s arguments, one of which rests on an analogy with the presumption of innocence, fail.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Bringing the Body Back to Sexual Ethics.Anne Barnhill - 2013 - Hypatia 28 (1):1-17.
    The body and bodily experience make little appearance in analytic moral philosophy. This is true even of analytic sexual ethics—the one area of ethical inquiry we might have expected to give a starring role to bodily experience. I take a small step toward remedying that by identifying one way in which the bodily experience of sex is ethically significant: some of the physical actions of sex have a default expressive significance, conveying trust, affection, care, sensitivity, enjoyment, and pleasure. When people (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations