Switch to: References

Citations of:

The myth of simplicity

Englewood Cliffs, N.J.,: Prentice-Hall (1963)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The architecture of complexity: A new blueprint.Peter Turney - 1989 - Synthese 79 (3):515 - 542.
    The logic of scientific discovery is now a concern of computer scientists, as well as philosophers. In the computational approach to inductive inference, theories are treated as algorithms (computer programs), and the goal is to find the simplest algorithm that can generate the given data. Both computer scientists and philosophers want a measure of simplicity, such that simple theories are more likely to be true than complex theories. I attempt to provide such a measure here. I define a measure of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Idealisierte erklärungen.Manfred Tietzel - 1986 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 17 (2):315-321.
    Idealized explanations are the one subtype of incomplete explanations which is most frequently used in the empirical sciences and at the same time least analyzed in philosphy of science. It is argued that idealized explanations, while having the same logical structure as adequate explanations, differ from these in the mode of validity of the argument. Whereas an adequate explanation shows why the occurrence of some event had to be expected, an idealized explanation argues that a certain event would occur if (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reclaiming the human stratum, acknowledging the complexity of social behaviour: From the linguistic turn to the social cube in theory of decision-making.Touko Piiparinen - 2006 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 36 (4):425–452.
    Roy Bhaskar's Social Cube model based on critical realist philosophy has not been dealt with in theory of decision-making at any length, nor has it raised any notable debate in social theory in general. The model demonstrates that decision-making is regulated and transformed by a constantly evolving complexity of mechanisms emerging from physical, mental, material, human and social levels of reality. With the help of this device, Graham Allison's argument against the Rational Actor Model that decisions are not so much (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bunge's theory of partial truth is no such thing.David Miller - 1977 - Philosophical Studies 31 (2):147 - 150.
  • The simplicity of theories: Its degree and form. [REVIEW]James W. McAllister - 1991 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 22 (1):1-14.
    Almost all commentators acknowledge that among the grounds on which scientists perform theory-choices are criteria of simplicity. In general, simplicity is regarded either as only a logico-empirical quality of a theory, diagnostic of the theory's future predictive success, or as a purely aesthetic or otherwise extra-empirical property of it. This paper attempts to demonstrate that the simplicity-criteria applied in scientific practice include both a logico-empirical and a quasi-aesthetic criterion: to conflate these in an account of scientists' theory-choice is to court (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Truth and beauty in scientific reason.James W. Mcallister - 1989 - Synthese 78 (1):25 - 51.
    A rationalist and realist model of scientific revolutions will be constructed by reference to two categories of criteria of theory-evaluation, denominated indicators of truth and of beauty. Whereas indicators of truth are formulateda priori and thus unite science in the pursuit of verisimilitude, aesthetic criteria are inductive constructs which lag behind the progression of theories in truthlikeness. Revolutions occur when the evaluative divergence between the two categories of criteria proves too wide to be recomposed or overlooked. This model of revolutions (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • How's of why's and why's of how's: Relation of method and cause in inquiry.Roberta Kevelson - 1988 - Synthese 74 (1):91 - 106.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Geochronometrie und geometrodynamik.Bernulf Kanitscheider - 1973 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 4 (2):261-302.
    Die Frage, ob die Gültigkeit alternativer begrifflicher Strukturen empirisch entscheidbar oder eine Sache der willkürlichen Festsetzung ist, wird, eingeschränkt auf den Fall der physikalischen Geometrie, diskutiert. Die erkenntnistheoretischen Komponenten der empirischen Bestimmung von metrischen und topologischen Eigenschaften des physikalischen Raumes werden in der neueren Wissenschaftstheorie verfolgt. In Anschluß an die Auseinandersetzung zwischen A. Grünbaum und H. Putnam wird eine Interpretation des semantischen Status des Kongruenzprädikates vorgeschlagen, die Schwierigkeiten im Verhältnis von Intension und Extension dieses Terms beseitigen soll. Bei der Konfrontation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Systematic realism.C. A. Hooker - 1974 - Synthese 26 (3-4):409 - 497.
  • How to investigate the underpinnings of sciences? The case of the element chlorine.Sarah Hijmans & Jean-Pierre Llored - 2020 - Foundations of Chemistry 22 (3):447-456.
    In recent publications, Harré and Llored Challenges of cultural psychology, Routledge, London, pp 189–206, 2018a; Philosophy, 93:167–186, 2018b; The analysis of practices, Cambridge Scholars Publishing, Newcastle upon Tyne, 2019) take the role of philosophy of science as a digging out of the ‘hinges’, that are the tacit elements of a discipline. In this perspective, the philosophy of chemistry consists, at least partly, in making explicit the hinges on which chemistry turns and in examining their origins and logical status. In this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hierarchy theory: A vision, vocabulary, and epistemology by Valerie Ahl and T.F.H. Allen.V. Cs�nyi - 1999 - Complexity 4 (6):29-30.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Social creativity.V. Csányi - 1991 - World Futures 32 (2):85-93.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Evolution: Unfolding a metaphor.V. Csányi - 1993 - World Futures 38 (1):75-87.
    (1993). Evolution: Unfolding a metaphor. World Futures: Vol. 38, Theoretical Achievements and Practical Applications of General Evolutionary Theory, pp. 75-87.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophical problems in linguistics.Mario Bunge - 1984 - Erkenntnis 21 (2):107-173.
  • Realism and antirealism in social science.Mario Bunge - 1993 - Theory and Decision 35 (3):207-235.
    Up until recently social scientists took it for granted that their task was to account for the social world as objectively as possible: they were realists in practice if not always in their methodological sermons. This situation started to change in the 1960s, when a number of antirealist philosophies made inroads into social studies. -/- This paper examines critically the following kinds of antirealism: subjectivism, conventionalism, fictionism, social constructivism, relativism, and hermeneutics. An attempt is made to show that these philosophies (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Quantitative Parsimony and Explanatory Power.Baker Alan - 2003 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (2):245-259.
    The desire to minimize the number of individual new entities postulated is often referred to as quantitative parsimony. Its influence on the default hypotheses formulated by scientists seems undeniable. I argue that there is a wide class of cases for which the preference for quantitatively parsimonious hypotheses is demonstrably rational. The justification, in a nutshell, is that such hypotheses have greater explanatory power than less parsimonious alternatives. My analysis is restricted to a class of cases I shall refer to as (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Third World Citizens and the Information Technology Revolution.Nicolas Adam - 2012 - Journal of Critical Realism 11 (4):515-522.
    Third World Citizens and the Information Technology Revolution Content Type Journal Article Category Review Pages 515-522 DOI 10.1558/jcr.v11i4.515 Authors Nicolas Adam, Centre d’études sur l’intégration et la mondialisation, Université du Québec à Montréal, 400, rue Sainte-Catherine Est, Pavillon Hubert-Aquin, 1er étage, bureau A-1560, Montréal H2L 2C5 Canada Journal Journal of Critical Realism Online ISSN 1572-5138 Print ISSN 1476-7430 Journal Volume Volume 11 Journal Issue Volume 11, Number 4 / 2012.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The problem of model selection and scientific realism.Stanislav Larski - unknown
    This thesis has two goals. Firstly, we consider the problem of model selection for the purposes of prediction. In modern science predictive mathematical models are ubiquitous and can be found in such diverse fields as weather forecasting, economics, ecology, mathematical psychology, sociology, etc. It is often the case that for a given domain of inquiry there are several plausible models, and the issue then is how to discriminate between them – this is the problem of model selection. We consider approaches (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark