Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Belief, Credence, and Pragmatic Encroachment.Jacob Ross & Mark Schroeder - 2014 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (2):259-288.
    This paper compares two alternative explanations of pragmatic encroachment on knowledge (i.e., the claim that whether an agent knows that p can depend on pragmatic factors). After reviewing the evidence for such pragmatic encroachment, we ask how it is best explained, assuming it obtains. Several authors have recently argued that the best explanation is provided by a particular account of belief, which we call pragmatic credal reductivism. On this view, what it is for an agent to believe a proposition is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   207 citations  
  • Actions, Reasons, and Intentions: Overcoming Davidson's Ontological Prejudice.John Michael McGuire - 2007 - Dialogue 46 (3):459-479.
    This article defends the idea that causal relations between reasons and actions are wholly irrelevant to the explanatory efficacy of reason-explanations. The analysis of reason-explanations provided in this article shows that the so-called “problem of explanatory force” is solved, not by putative causal relations between the reasons for which agents act and their actions, but rather by the intentions that agents necessarily have when they act for a reason. Additionally, the article provides a critique of the principal source of support (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The SMA: A “supplementary motor” or a “supramotor” area?Mario Wiesendanger - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):600-601.
  • What are voluntary movements made of?Ian Q. Whishaw - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):290-291.
  • Medial versus lateral motor control.Michael Weinrich - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):600-600.
  • Birdsong: Variations that follow rules.Dietmar Todt & Henrike Hultsch - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):289-290.
  • Sensorimotor reference frames and physiological attractors.René Thom - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):289-289.
  • New findings on the behavior of supplementary motor area neurons recorded from task-performing monkeys.Jun Tanji - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):599-600.
  • Considering Causalisms.Andrew Sneddon - 2001 - Dialogue 40 (2):343.
    Depuis 1963, le causalisme a été l'approche dominante en théorie de l'action. Il est possible, cependant, de distinguer diverses sortes de causalisme. La version dominante, que j'appelle CTA, essaie de trouver une analyse causale de l'action. Une version plus restreinte — le causalismeR — se montre récalcitrante à ce genre d'entreprise et se contente d'essayer d'expliquer en quel sens on peut traiter comme causales les explications par les raisons. J'examine ici les motivations sous-jacentes à CTA, ainsi que plusieurs de ses (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Naturalizing the context for interpreting SMA function.John P. Scholz, M. T. Turvey & J. A. S. Kelso - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):598-598.
  • Neuronal processes involved in initiating a behavioral act.Wolfram Schultz - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):599-599.
  • Describing behavior: A new label for an old wine?Wolfgang M. Schleidt - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):288-289.
  • Basic deviance reconsidered.Markus E. Schlosser - 2007 - Analysis 67 (3):186–194.
    Most contemporary philosophers of action agree on the following claims. Firstly, the possibility of deviant or wayward causal chains poses a serious problem for the standard-causal theory of action. Secondly, we can distinguish between different kinds of deviant causal chains in the theory of action. In particular, we can distinguish between cases of basic and cases of consequential deviance. Thirdly, the problem of consequential deviance admits of a fairly straightforward solution, whereas the possibility of basic deviance constitutes a separate and (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Free will and motor subroutines: Too much for a small area.Giacomo Rizzolatti - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):597-597.
  • From psychopharmacology to neuropsychopharmacology: Adapting behavioral terminology to neural events.George V. Rebec - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):287-288.
  • Participation of SMA neurons in a “self-paced” motor act.R. Porter - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):596-597.
  • Construal level and free will beliefs shape perceptions of actors' proximal and distal intent.Jason E. Plaks & Jeffrey S. Robinson - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6:135664.
    Two components of lay observers’ calculus of moral judgment are proximal intent (the actor’s mind is focused on performing the action) and distal intent (the actor’s mind is focused on the broader goal). What causes observers to prioritize one form of intent over the other? The authors observed whether construal level (Studies 1-2) and beliefs about free will (Studies 3-4) would influence participants’ sensitivity to the actor’s proximal versus distal intent. In four studies, participants read scenarios in which the actor’s (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The yin and yang of behavioral analysis.Sergio M. Pellis - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):286-286.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Architecture and connections of the premotor areas in the rhesus monkey.Deepak N. Pandya & Helen Barbas - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):595-596.
  • Human observation and human action.Darren Newtson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):285-285.
  • Preparation yes, intention no.E. J. Neafsey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):594-595.
  • Animal Mental Action: Planning Among Chimpanzees.Angelica Kaufmann - 2015 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6 (4):745-760.
    I offer an argument for what mental action may be like in nonhuman animals. Action planning is a type of mental action that involves a type of intention. Some intentions are the causal mental antecedents of proximal mental actions, and some intentions are the causal mental antecedents of distal mental actions. The distinction between these two types of “plan-states” is often spelled out in terms of mental content. The prominent view is that while proximal mental actions are caused by mental (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Time-based objective coding and human nonverbal behavior.Roger D. Masters - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):284-285.
  • Joint torque precedes the kinematic end result.William A. MacKay - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):283-284.
  • Somewhere in time – temporal factors in vertebrate movement analysis.Melvin Lyon - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):282-283.
  • A logic of intention and attempt.Emiliano Lorini & Andreas Herzig - 2008 - Synthese 163 (1):45 - 77.
    We present a modal logic called (logic of intention and attempt) in which we can reason about intention dynamics and intentional action execution. By exploiting the expressive power of , we provide a formal analysis of the relation between intention and action and highlight the pivotal role of attempt in action execution. Besides, we deal with the problems of instrumental reasoning and intention persistence.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Volitional processes in relation to the SMA.Benjamin Libet - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):592-594.
  • Animal motility: Gestalt or piecemeal assembly.Paul Leyhausen - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):282-282.
  • The starting function of the SMA.H. H. Kornhuber & L. Deecke - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):591-592.
  • Structure and function in the CNS.Peter H. Klopfer - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):281-282.
  • Actions and accidents.David Horst - 2015 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45 (3):300-325.
    In acting intentionally, it is no accident that one is doing what one intends to do. In this paper, I ask how to account for this non-accidentality requirement on intentional action. I argue that, for systematic reasons, the currently prevailing view of intentional action – the Causal Theory of Action – is ill-equipped to account for it. I end by proposing an alternative account, according to which an intention is a special kind of cause, one to which it is essential (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Shapes of behaviour.John G. Harries - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):279-281.
  • Perception and non-inferential knowledge of action.Thor Grünbaum - 2011 - Philosophical Explorations 14 (2):153 - 167.
    I present an account of how agents can know what they are doing when they intentionally execute object-oriented actions. When an agent executes an object-oriented intentional action, she uses perception in such a way that it can fulfil a justificatory role for her knowledge of her own action and it can fulfil this justificatory role without being inferentially linked to the cognitive states that it justifies. I argue for this proposal by meeting two challenges: in an agent's knowledge of her (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Systems and system interactions.J. A. Gray - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):591-591.
  • Where there is a ‘will,’ there is a way.Gary Goldberg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):601-615.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The natural geometry of a behavioral homology.Ilan Golani - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):291-308.
  • Supplementary motor area structure and function: review and hypotheses.Gary Goldberg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):567-588.
  • Dynamical systems theory and the mobility gradient: Information, homology and self-similar structure.Gary Goldberg - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):278-279.
  • The path to action.J. M. Fuster - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):589-591.
  • Bratman on identity over time and identification at a time.Christopher Evan Franklin - 2017 - Philosophical Explorations 20 (1):1-14.
    According to reductionists about agency, an agent’s bringing something about is reducible to states and events involving the agent bringing something about. Many have worried that reductionism cannot accommodate robust forms of agency, such as self-determination. One common reductionist answer to this worry contends that self-determining agents are identified with certain states and events, and so these states and events causing a decision counts as the agent’s self-determining the decision. In this paper, I discuss Michael Bratman’s well-known identification reductionist theory (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Alternative taxonomies in movement: Not only possible but critical.John C. Fentress - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):277-278.
  • Connecting invertebrate behavior, neurophysiology and evolution with Eshkol-Wachman movement notation.Zen Faulkes & Dorothy Hayman Paul - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):276-277.
  • Moving beyond words.Robert Fagen - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):275-276.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lewis’ Conditional Analysis of Dispositions Revisited and Revised.Markus E. Schlosser - 2018 - Acta Analytica 33 (2):241-253.
    The conditional analysis of dispositions is widely rejected, mainly due to counterexamples in which dispositions are either “finkish” or “masked.” David Lewis proposed a reformed conditional analysis. This view avoids the problem of finkish dispositions, but it fails to solve the problem of masking. I will propose a reformulation of Lewis’ analysis, and I will argue that this reformulation can easily be modified so that it avoids the problem of masking. In the final section, I will address the challenge that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The mobility gradient from a comparative phylogenetic perspective.David Eilam - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):274-275.
  • Understanding the mind's will.Antonio R. Damasio - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):589-589.
  • Dispositions, Abilities to Act, and Free Will: The New Dispositionalism.Randolph Clarke - 2009 - Mind 118 (470):323-351.
    This paper examines recent attempts to revive a classic compatibilist position on free will, according to which having an ability to perform a certain action is having a certain disposition. Since having unmanifested dispositions is compatible with determinism, having unexercised abilities to act, it is held, is likewise compatible. Here it is argued that although there is a kind of capacity to act possession of which is a matter of having a disposition, the new dispositionalism leaves unresolved the main points (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  • A prelude to the Goldberg variations on motor organization.Jason W. Brown - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):588-589.
  • Meditation and the Scope of Mental Action.Michael Brent & Candace Upton - 2019 - Philosophical Psychology 32 (1):52-71.
    While philosophers of mind have devoted abundant time and attention to questions of content and consciousness, philosophical questions about the nature and scope of mental action have been relatively neglected. Galen Strawson’s account of mental action, arguably the most well-known extant account, holds that cognitive mental action consists in triggering the delivery of content to one’s field of consciousness. However, Strawson fails to recognize several distinct types of mental action that might not reduce to triggering content delivery. In this paper, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Agent causation as a solution to the problem of action.Michael Brent - 2017 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 47 (5):656-673.
    My primary aim is to defend a nonreductive solution to the problem of action. I argue that when you are performing an overt bodily action, you are playing an irreducible causal role in bringing about, sustaining, and controlling the movements of your body, a causal role best understood as an instance of agent causation. Thus, the solution that I defend employs a notion of agent causation, though emphatically not in defence of an account of free will, as most theories of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations