Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Aristotle's Theory of Abstraction.Allan Bäck - 2014 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    This book investigates Aristotle’s views on abstraction and explores how he uses it. In this work, the author follows Aristotle in focusing on the scientific detail first and then approaches the metaphysical claims, and so creates a reconstructed theory that explains many puzzles of Aristotle’s thought. Understanding the details of his theory of relations and abstraction further illuminates his theory of universals. Some of the features of Aristotle’s theory of abstraction developed in this book include: abstraction is a relation; perception (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Images, Appearances, and Phantasia in Aristotle.Krisanna M. Scheiter - 2012 - Phronesis 57 (3):251-278.
    Abstract Aristotle's account of Phantasia in De Anima 3.3 is notoriously difficult to decipher. At one point he describes Phantasia as a capacity for producing images, but then later in the same chapter it is clear Phantasia is supposed to explain appearances, such as why the sun appears to be a foot wide. Many commentators argue that images cannot explain appearances, and so they claim that Aristotle is using Phantasia in two different ways. In this paper I argue that images (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Euclides e a geometria do raio visual.Guilherme Rodrigues Neto - 2013 - Scientiae Studia 11 (4):873-892.
    Este ensaio introdutório faz uma breve apresentação do tratado de óptica atribuído a Euclides de Alexandria, inserindo-o no contexto das teorias sobre a visão formuladas pelas doutrinas filosóficas antigas. Ressalta-se o antagonismo entre a análise geométrica da visão, empreendida por Euclides, e as considerações filosóficas acerca dos processos físicos subjacentes à sensação visual. Pretende-se mostrar que o objeto da óptica euclidiana é a percepção visual daquilo que Aristóteles denomina "sensível comum". This introductory essay provides an abridged presentation of the optical (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle's Parts of Animals 2. 16. 659 b 13–19: is it Authentic?Anthony Preus - 1968 - Classical Quarterly 18 (02):270-.
    The purpose of this article is to present arguments which indicate that PA 2. 16. 659b13–19 may not be authentic.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle's Parts of Animals 2. 16. 659 b 13–19: is it Authentic?Anthony Preus - 1968 - Classical Quarterly 18 (2):270-278.
    The purpose of this article is to present arguments which indicate that PA 2. 16. 659b13–19 may not be authentic.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle’s Infallible Perception.Benjamin Robert Koons - 2019 - Apeiron 52 (4):415-443.
    In the De Anima, Aristotle claims that the five senses are infallible about their proper objects. I contend that this claim means that sight is infallible about its proper object in its most specific form, i. e. sight is infallible about red or green and not merely about color in general. This robust claim is justified by Aristotle’s teleological principle that nature does nothing in vain. Additionally, drawing on Aristotle’s comparison of perception and one’s understanding of the essences, I defend (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Truth and Falsity of Three Sorts of Perception.Evan Keeling - 2022 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 39 (4):305-322.
    Aristotle's theory of perception is complicated by the fact that he recognizes three kinds of perceptible object: special, common, and incidental, all of which have different levels of reliability. Focusing on De Anima 3.3, 428b17–25, this paper discusses why these three sorts of perception are true and false. It argues that perceptions of special objects can be false because of the blind-spot phenomenon and that common objects are typically perceived as predicated of an incidental object. This helps explain why perceptions (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle and Alexander on Perceptual Error.Mark A. Johnstone - 2015 - Phronesis 60 (3):310-338.
    Aristotle sometimes claims that the perception of special perceptibles by their proper sense is unerring. This claim is striking, since it might seem that we quite often misperceive things like colours, sounds and smells. Aristotle also claims that the perception of common perceptibles is more prone to error than the perception of special perceptibles. This is puzzling in its own right, and also places constraints on the interpretation of. I argue that reading Alexander of Aphrodisias on perceptual error can help (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The ten modes of aenesidemus and the myth of ancient scepticism.Stephen Gaukroger - 1995 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 3 (2):371 – 387.
  • The role of natural philosophy in the development of Locke's empiricism.Stephen Gaukroger - 2009 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 17 (1):55 – 83.
    (2009). The Role of Natural Philosophy in the Development of Locke's Empiricism. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 17, No. 1, pp. 55-83.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle on the function of sense perception.Stephen Gaukroger - 1981 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 12 (1):75-89.
  • Galileo's telescopic observations of Venus and Mars.Alan Chalmers - 1985 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (2):175-184.
  • De anima II 5.Myles F. Burnyeat - 2002 - Phronesis 47 (1):28-90.
    This is a close scrutiny of De Anima II 5, led by two questions. First, what can be learned from so long and intricate a discussion about the neglected problem of how to read an Aristotelian chapter? Second, what can the chapter, properly read, teach us about some widely debated issues in Aristotle's theory of perception? I argue that it refutes two claims defended by Martha Nussbaum, Hilary Putnam, and Richard Sorabji: that when Aristotle speaks of the perceiver becoming like (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Aristotle on pre-Platonic theories of sense-perception and knowledge.Luis Andrés Bredlow - 2010 - Filosofia Unisinos 11 (3):204-224.
  • Aristotle’s Naïve Somatism.Alain E. Ducharme - unknown
    Aristotle’s Naïve Somatism is a re-interpretation of Aristotle’s cognitive psychology in light of certain presuppositions he holds about the living animal body. The living animal body is presumed to be sensitive, and Aristotle grounds his account of cognition in a rudimentary proprioceptive awareness one has of her body. With that presupposed metaphysics under our belts, we are in a position to see that Aristotle in de Anima (cognition chapters at least) has a di erent explanatory aim in view than that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Real Knowledge. The problem of content in neural epistemics.J. J. M. Sleutels - unknown
  • Hume and human error.Mark Hooper - unknown