Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Grammar of Binding in the languages of the world: Innate or learned?Peter Cole, Gabriella Hermon & Yanti - 2015 - Cognition 141 (C):138-160.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On one as an anaphor.Stephen Neale - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):353-354.
  • The child's trigger experience: Degree-0 learnability.David Lightfoot - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):321-334.
    According to a “selective” (as opposed to “instructive”) model of human language capacity, people come to know more than they experience. The discrepancy between experience and eventual capacity (the “poverty of the stimulus”) is bridged by genetically provided information. Hence any hypothesis about the linguistic genotype (or “Universal Grammar,” UG) has consequences for what experience is needed and what form people's mature capacities (or “grammars”) will take. This BBS target article discusses the “trigger experience,” that is, the experience that actually (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • How adult second language learning differs from child first language development.Harald Clahsen & Pieter Muysken - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):721-723.
    We argue that the model developed in Epstein et al.'s target article does not explain differences between child first language (LI) acquisition and adult second language (L2) acquisition. We therefore sketch an alternative view, originally developed in Clahsen and Muysken (1989), in the light of new empirical findings and theoretical developments.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The comparative simplicity of tool-use and its implications for human evolution.Thomas Wynn - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):576-577.
  • Why degree-0?Wendy Wilkins - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):362-363.
  • Linguistic variation and learnability.Edwin Williams - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):363-364.
  • In defense of exaptation.Wendy Wilkins & Jennie Dumford - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):763-764.
  • UG, the L1, and questions of evidence.Lydia White - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):745-746.
    Epstein, Flynn, and Martohardjono's presentation of the principal approaches to UG access in L2 acquisition is misleading; they have neglected the possibility that the L1 grammar forms the learner's initial representation of the L2, with subsequent modifications constrained by UG. Furthermore, their experimental data are open to several interpretations and are consistent with a number of different positions in the field.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why degree-0?Thomas Wasow - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):361-362.
  • Observing obsolescence.Nigel Vincent - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):360-361.
  • Syntactic processes in speech production: the retrieval of grammatical gender.Jos J. A. van Berkum - 1997 - Cognition 64 (2):115-152.
  • Partial transfer, not partial access.Anne Vainikka & Martha Young-Scholten - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):744-745.
    Our results support the idea that adults have access to the principles and parameters of Universal Grammar (UG), contrary to Epstein et al.'s misrepresentation of our work as involvingpartial access toUG. For both LI and L2 acquisition, functional projections appear to develop in a gradual fashion, but in L2 acquisition there ispartial transferin that the lowest projection (VP) is transferred from the speaker's LI.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why chimps matter to language origin.Ib Ulbaek - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):762-763.
  • Towards characterizing what the L2 learner knows.Esther Torrego - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):744-744.
    This target article is mostly a presentation of experimental research devoted to the larger issue of the role of Universal Grammar in second language learning. Deliberately excluding the aspects of human cognition that makes second language (L2) so variant, Epstein et al. focus on what the learners may know and how they come to know it. This is the aspect of Epstein et al.'s work which is more limiting, and potentially more interesting.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward an adaptationist psycholinguistics.John Tooby & Leda Cosmides - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):760-762.
  • Objects are analogous to words, not phonemes or grammatical categories.Michael Tomasello - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):575-576.
  • Grammar yes, generative grammar no.Michael Tomasello - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):759-760.
  • “Full access” and the history of linguistics.Margaret Thomas - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):743-744.
    This commentary addresses two pervasive misconceptions which emerge in Epstein et al.'s target article: (1) that study of second language acquisition (SLA) began in the mid-twentieth century; (2) that SLA has only recently become able to contribute to linguistic theory. There is abundant historical counterevidence; I argue that (1) and (2) obscure the legitimacy of Epstein et al.'s “full access” hypothesis.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are rhythms of human cerebral development “traveling waves”?Robert W. Thatcher - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):575-575.
  • The view of language.Michael Studdert-Kennedy - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):758-759.
  • What's a trigger?Edward P. Stabler - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):358-360.
  • Appreciating the poverty of the stimulus in second language acquisition.Rex A. Sprouse - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):742-743.
    The most compelling evidence for Epstein et al.'s central thesis that adult second language acquisition is constrained by the innate cognitive structures that constrain native language acquisition would be evidence of poverty of the stimulus. Although there are studies that point to such evidence, Epstein et al.'s primary form of argumentation, targetlike performance by second-language acquiring adults, is much less convincing.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The evolution of the language faculty: A paradox and its solution.Dan Sperber - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):756-758.
  • On gradience and optionality in non-native grammars.Antonella Sorace - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):741-742.
    Epstein et al.'s “full access to Universal Grammar” position is conceptually and empirically problematic. Its shortcomings are illustrated through a brief discussion of the following issues: (1) initial versus final states of grammatical knowledge in a second language, (2) knowledge of gradience of grainmaticality, (3) optionality and retention in non-native grammars, and (4) the empirical measurement of syntactic knowledge.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Anatomizing the rhinoceros.Elliott Sober - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):764-765.
  • Data on language input: Incomprehensible omission indeed!Catherine E. Snow & Michael Tomasello - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):357-358.
  • Metalinguistic ability and primary linguistic data.M. A. Sharwood Smith - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):740-741.
    The role of metalinguistic ability in L2 development is seriously underestimated. It may be seen both (1) as a means of initiating or boosting the flow of primary linguistic data and (2) as a generator of substitute knowledge (derived, but epistemologically distinct from domain-specific knowledge) that may compete with or compensate for perceived gaps in the learners current underlying competence. It cannot serve as a simple means of distinguishing the rival theoretical positions.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quasiregularity and Its Discontents: The Legacy of the Past Tense Debate.Mark S. Seidenberg & David C. Plaut - 2014 - Cognitive Science 38 (6):1190-1228.
    Rumelhart and McClelland's chapter about learning the past tense created a degree of controversy extraordinary even in the adversarial culture of modern science. It also stimulated a vast amount of research that advanced the understanding of the past tense, inflectional morphology in English and other languages, the nature of linguistic representations, relations between language and other phenomena such as reading and object recognition, the properties of artificial neural networks, and other topics. We examine the impact of the Rumelhart and McClelland (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A Probabilistic Constraints Approach to Language Acquisition and Processing.Mark S. Seidenberg & Maryellen C. MacDonald - 1999 - Cognitive Science 23 (4):569-588.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Heritage language and linguistic theory.Gregory Scontras, Zuzanna Fuchs & Maria Polinsky - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Now for some facts, with a focus on development and an explicit role for the L1.Bonnie D. Schwartz - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):739-740.
    Curiously, two central areas are unaddressed by Epstein et al.: (i) L1A–L2A differences; (ii) L2 development. Here, findings relevant to (i) and (ii) – as well as their significance – are discussed. Together these form the basis for contesting Epstein et al.'s “Full Access” approach, but nonetheless analyses of the L2 data argue for UG-constrained L2A. Also discussed is the inadequacy of accounts (like Epstein et al.'s) without an explicit and prominent role for the L1.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language acquisition: Dubious assumptions and a specious explanatory principle.I. M. Schlesinger - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):355-356.
  • Hierarchical organization in grammar.Leonard Rolfe - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):574-574.
  • On the format for parameters.Luigi Rizzi - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):355-356.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Arbitrariness no argument against adaption.Mark Ridley - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):756-756.
  • Systematicity, but not compositionality: Examining the emergence of linguistic structure in children and adults using iterated learning.Limor Raviv & Inbal Arnon - 2018 - Cognition 181 (C):160-173.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Compositional structure can emerge without generational transmission.Limor Raviv, Antje Meyer & Shiri Lev-Ari - 2019 - Cognition 182 (C):151-164.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On the concept of animal innovation and the challenge of studying innovation in the wild.Grant Ramsey, Meredith L. Bastian & Carel van Schaik - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (4):425-432.
    The commentaries have both drawn out the implications of, and challenged, our definition and operationalization of innovation. In this response, we reply to these concerns, discuss the differences between our operationalization and the preexisting operationalization if innovation, and make suggestions for the advancement of the challenging and exciting field of animal innovation.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Animal innovation defined and operationalized.Grant Ramsey, Meredith L. Bastian & Carel van Schaik - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (4):393-407.
    Innovation is a key component of most definitions of culture and intelligence. Additionally, innovations may affect a species' ecology and evolution. Nonetheless, conceptual and empirical work on innovation has only recently begun. In particular, largely because the existing operational definition (first occurrence in a population) requires long-term studies of populations, there has been no systematic study of innovation in wild animals. To facilitate such study, we have produced a new definition of innovation: Innovation is the process that generates in an (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • On the coevolution of language and social competence.David Premack - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):754-756.
  • “Gavagai!” or the future history of the animal language controversy.David Premack - 1985 - Cognition 19 (3):207-296.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Gavagai!: Or, the Future History of the Animal Language Controversy.David Premack - 1986 - MIT Press.
    In this witty and fascinating book, Premack examines arguments over whether humans are unique because we can talk.
  • Goal directed behavior in the sensorimotor and language hierarchies.David M. W. Powers - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):572-574.
  • Conceptual representations and figurative language in language shift.Maïa Ponsonnet - 2017 - Cognitive Linguistics 28 (4):631-671.
    This article explores the correlations between linguistic figurative features and their corresponding conceptual representations, by considering their respective continuities and discontinuities in language shift. I compare the figurative encoding of emotions in Kriol, a creole of northern Australia, with those of Dalabon, one of the languages replaced by this creole, with a particular focus on evidence from metaphorical gestures. The conclusions are three-fold. Firstly, the prominent figurative association between the body and the emotions observed in Dalabon is, overall, not matched (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Natural language and natural selection.Steven Pinker & Paul Bloom - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):707-27.
    Many people have argued that the evolution of the human language faculty cannot be explained by Darwinian natural selection. Chomsky and Gould have suggested that language may have evolved as the by-product of selection for other abilities or as a consequence of as-yet unknown laws of growth and form. Others have argued that a biological specialization for grammar is incompatible with every tenet of Darwinian theory – that it shows no genetic variation, could not exist in any intermediate forms, confers (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   598 citations  
  • Issues in the evolution of the human language faculty.Steven Pinker & Paul Bloom - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):765-784.
  • An ideological battle over modals and quantifiers.Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):752-754.
  • Complexity and adaptation.David Pesetsky & Ned Block - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):750-752.
  • The emergence of homo loquens and the laws of physics.Carlos P. Otero - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):747-750.