Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Berkeley's Immaterialism and Kant's Transcendental Idealism.M. R. Ayers - 1982 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 13:51-69.
    Ever since its first publication critics of Kant'sCritique of Pure Reasonhave been struck by certain strong formal resemblances between transcendental idealism and Berkeley's immaterialism. Both philosophers hold that the sensible world is mind-dependent, and that from this very mind-dependence we can draw a refutation of scepticism of the senses.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Berkeley on the Act-Object Distinction.Thomas M. Lennon - 2001 - Dialogue 40 (4):651-668.
    RésuméMoore attribuah l'idéalisme de Berkeley à sa négligence de la distinction entre l'acte d'appréhension et son objet. Bien que Berkeley ait justement tracé cette distinction dans le premier Dialogue, et l'ait rejetée, peu s'en sont aperçu, et ceux qui l'ont remarqué lui reprochent habituellement de confondre l'acte d'appréhension avec une action. La thèse ici développée est que Berkeley n'est pas coupable de cette confusion et qu'il rejette la distinction, en fait, pour de bonnes raisons à caractére empiriste, qui ont à (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The meaning of representation in animal memory.H. L. Roitblat - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):353-372.
    A representation is a remnant of previous experience that allows that experience to affect later behavior. This paper develops a metatheoretical view of representation and applies it to issues concerning representation in animals. To describe a representational system one must specify the following: thedomainor range of situations in the represented world to which the system applies; thecontentor set of features encoded and preserved by the system; thecodeor transformational rules relating features of the representation to the corresponding features of the represented (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   312 citations  
  • The heuristic value of representation.Thomas R. Zentall - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):393-394.
  • Mind the brain.Martha Wilson - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):393-393.
  • Internal representations and indeterminacy: A skeptical view.William R. Uttal - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):392-393.
  • Animal versus human minds.H. S. Terrace - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):391-392.
  • In the beginning was the word.J. E. R. Staddon - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):390-391.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Historicism, behaviorism, and the conceptual status of memory representations in animals.Charles P. Shimp - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):389-390.
  • Expectancy: The endogenous source of anticipatory activities, including “pseudoconditioned” responses.Patrick J. Sheafor - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):387-389.
  • Metatheory of animal behavior.Erwin M. Segal - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):386-387.
  • Samuel Clarke on Agent Causation, Voluntarism, and Occasionalism.Andrea Sangiacomo - 2018 - Science in Context 31 (4):421-456.
    ArgumentThis paper argues that Samuel Clarke's account of agent causation (i) provides a philosophical basis for moderate voluntarism, and (ii) both leads to and benefits from the acceptance of partial occasionalism as a model of causation for material beings. Clarke's account of agent causation entails that for an agent to be properly called an agent (i.e. causally efficacious), it is essential that the agent is free to choose whether to act or not. This freedom is compatible with the existence of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The logic of representation.William W. Rozeboom - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):385-386.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Vasubandhu's idealism: An encounter between philosophy and religion.Ornan Rotem - 1993 - Asian Philosophy 3 (1):15 – 28.
    Abstract According to idealism the world, as we perceive it, is in effect a creation of the mind. There are many different forms of idealism and this paper investigates one form of idealism that was advocated by the 4th century Buddhist Yog?c?rin Vasubandhu and one not unfamiliar in the west, especially in the works of George Berkeley. This paper suggests that when idealism, as a metaphysical theory, is set within a soteriological framework, as is the case with Vasubandhu, it serves (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Representations and cognition.H. L. Roitblat - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):394-406.
  • Premature closure of controversial issues concerning animal memory representations.William A. Roberts - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):384-385.
  • Affordances and Phenomenal Character in Spatial Perception.Simon Prosser - 2011 - Philosophical Review 120 (4):475-513.
    Intentionalism is the view that the phenomenal character of a conscious experience is wholly determined by, or even reducible to, its representational content. In this essay I put forward a version of intentionalism that allows (though does not require) the reduction of phenomenal character to representational content. Unlike other reductionist theories, however, it does not require the acceptance of phenomenal externalism (the view that phenomenal character does not supervene on the internal state of the subject). According the view offered here, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • On the content of representations.R. J. Nelson - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):384-384.
  • Some thoughts on the proper foundations for the study of cognition in animals.Lynn Nadel - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):383-384.
  • A la représentation du temps perdu.John C. Marshall - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):382-383.
  • Cognitive psychology's representation of behaviorism.A. W. Logue - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):381-382.
  • Memory representations in animals: Some metatheoretical issues.Roy Lachman & Janet L. Lachman - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):380-381.
  • Representations as metaphiers.Julian Jaynes - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):379-380.
  • Comparative cognition revisited.Stewart H. Hulse - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):379-379.
  • Defending Berkeley's divine ideas.Marc A. Hight - 2005 - Philosophia 33 (1-4):97-128.
  • Some distinctions among representations.M. Gopnik - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):378-379.
  • Representation: A concept that fills no gaps.Robert Epstein - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):377-378.
  • Mach's principle, relative motion, and fundamental numbers of physics.R. E. Eaves - 1976 - Foundations of Physics 6 (5):613-620.
    Mach's principle is discussed as a fundamental statement on kinematics, and an apparent contradiction is identified in the Lorentz-Minkowski form of the inertial metric. To resolve the incompatibility, length is redefined so that the speed of light is a field-dependent variable, although still constant for all inertial observers at a point in space-time. Gravitational theories with variableG are considered, and it is shown that a redefinition of length and time results in constantG and variablec.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The informational character of representations.Fred Dretske - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):376-377.
  • Memory: A matter of fitness.Juan D. Delius - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):375-376.
  • Behaviorism's new cognitive representations: Paradigm regained.Arthur C. Danto - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):375-375.
  • Antimisrepresentationalism.A. Charles Catania - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):374-375.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Structuring Logical Space.Alejandro Pérez Carballo - 2014 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 92 (2):460-491.
    I develop a non-representationalist account of mathematical thought, on which the point of mathematical theorizing is to provide us with the conceptual capacity to structure and articulate information about the physical world in an epistemically useful way. On my view, accepting a mathematical theory is not a matter of having a belief about some subject matter; it is rather a matter of structuring logical space, in a sense to be made precise. This provides an elegant account of the cognitive utility (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Memory and rules in animal serial learning.E. J. Capaldi - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):373-373.
  • The homiletical context of Butler's moral philosophy.Alan Brinton - 1993 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 1 (2):83 – 107.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Misrepresenting behaviorism.Marc N. Branch - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):372-373.
  • The logical form of perception sentences.John Bacon - 1979 - Synthese 41 (2):271 - 308.
    The perceptual logic of j hintikka and r thomason is imbedded in a more general framework of quantification over individual-concepts. two intensional predicates for physical individuation and perceptual individuation are required in place of thomason's two variable-sorts. objectual perception of x by s is then definable as "for some y there is a perceptually individuated object z, in fact identical with x, such that s perceives that y is z.".
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Existence Assumptions and Logical Principles: Choice Operators in Intuitionistic Logic.Corey Edward Mulvihill - 2015 - Dissertation, University of Waterloo
    Hilbert’s choice operators τ and ε, when added to intuitionistic logic, strengthen it. In the presence of certain extensionality axioms they produce classical logic, while in the presence of weaker decidability conditions for terms they produce various superintuitionistic intermediate logics. In this thesis, I argue that there are important philosophical lessons to be learned from these results. To make the case, I begin with a historical discussion situating the development of Hilbert’s operators in relation to his evolving program in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Los esquemas de los conceptos empíricos y matemáticos como procedimientos de síntesis gobernados por reglas conceptuales.Martín Arias Albisu - 2014 - Studia Kantiana 17:74-103.
    El objetivo del presente artículo es ofrecer una interpretación de la doctrina del esquematismo de los conceptos empíricos y matemáticos presentada por Kant en su Crítica de la razón pura. Mostramos que los esquemas de los conceptos empíricos y matemáticos son procedimientos de síntesis gobernados por reglas conceptuales. Aunque no consideramos que esta doctrina kantiana carece de problemas, nuestro trabajo muestra que: 1) esos esquemas pueden distinguirse rigurosamente de sus correspondientes conceptos; 2) esos esquemas no son entidades superfluas. Estas conclusiones (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark