Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Expected comparative utility theory: A new theory of instrumental rationality.David Robert - manuscript
    This paper aims to address the question of how one ought to choose when one is uncertain about what outcomes will result from one’s choices, but when one can nevertheless assign probabilities to the different possible outcomes. These choices are commonly referred to as choices (or decisions) under risk. I assume in this paper that one ought to make instrumentally rational choices—more precisely, one ought to adopt suitable means to one’s morally permissible ends. Expected utility (EU) theory is generally accepted (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Expected Comparative Utility Theory: A New Theory of Rational Choice.David Robert - 2018 - Philosophical Forum 49 (1):19-37.
    In this paper, I argue for a new normative theory of rational choice under risk, namely expected comparative utility (ECU) theory. I first show that for any choice option, a, and for any state of the world, G, the measure of the choiceworthiness of a in G is the comparative utility (CU) of a in G—that is, the difference in utility, in G, between a and whichever alternative to a carries the greatest utility in G. On the basis of this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Making decisions about the future: Regret and the cognitive function of episodic memory.Christoph Hoerl & Teresa McCormack - 2016 - In Kourken Michaelian, Stanley B. Klein & Karl K. Szpunar (eds.), Seeing the Future: Theoretical Perspectives on Future-Oriented Mental Time Travel. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. pp. 241-266.
    In the recent literature on episodic memory, there has been increasing recognition of the need to provide an account of its adaptive function. In this context, it is sometimes argued that episodic memory is critical for certain forms of decision making about the future. We criticize existing accounts that try to give episodic memory a role in decision making, before giving a novel such account of our own. This turns on the thought of a link between episodic memory and the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A Parallel between Regret Theory and Outranking Methods for Multicriteria Decision Making Under Imprecise Information.Gül Özerol & Esra Karasakal - 2008 - Theory and Decision 65 (1):45-70.
    Incorporation of the behavioral issues of the decision maker (DM) is among the aspects that each Multicriteria Decision Making (MCDM) method implicitly or explicitly takes into account. As postulated by regret theory, the feelings of regret and rejoice are among the behavioral issues associated with the entire decision making process. Within the context of MCDM, the DM may feel regret, when the chosen alternative is compared with another one having at least one better criterion value. PROMETHEE II is a widely (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Experience of Regret and Disappointment.Marcel Zeelenberg, Wilco W. van Dijk, Antony S. R. Manstead & Joopvan der Pligt - 1998 - Cognition and Emotion 12 (2):221-230.
    Regret and disappointment have in common the fact that they are experienced when the outcome of a decision is unfavourable: They both concern “what might have been”, had things been different. However, some regret and disappointment theorists regard the differences between these emotions as important, arguing that they differ with respect to the conditions under which they are felt, and how they affect decision making. The goal of the present research was to examine whether and how these emotions also differ (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Anxiety and Decision Making with Delayed Resolution of Uncertainty.George Wu - 1999 - Theory and Decision 46 (2):159-199.
    In many real-world gambles, a non-trivial amount of time passes before the uncertainty is resolved but after a choice is made. An individual may have a preference between gambles with identical probability distributions over final outcomes if they differ in the timing of resolution of uncertainty. In this domain, utility consists not only of the consumption of outcomes, but also the psychological utility induced by an unresolved gamble. We term this utility anxiety. Since a reflective decision maker may want to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Mean-risk decision analysis.Paul Weirich - 1987 - Theory and Decision 23 (1):89-111.
  • Expected utility and risk.Paul Weirich - 1986 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (4):419-442.
    The rule to maximize expected utility is intended for decisions where options involve risk. In those decisions the decision maker's attitude toward risk is important, and the rule ought to take it into account. Allais's and Ellsberg's paradoxes, however, suggest that the rule ignores attitudes toward risk. This suggestion is supported by recent psychological studies of decisions. These studies present a great variety of cases where apparently rational people violate the rule because of aversion or attraction to risk. Here I (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Relatively robust decisions.Thomas A. Weber - 2022 - Theory and Decision 94 (1):35-62.
    It is natural for humans to judge the outcome of a decision under uncertainty as a percentage of an ex-post optimal performance. We propose a robust decision-making framework based on a relative performance index. It is shown that if the decision maker’s preferences satisfy quasisupermodularity, single-crossing, and a nondecreasing log-differences property, the worst-case relative performance index can be represented as the lower envelope of two extremal performance ratios. The latter is used to characterize the agent’s optimal robust decision, which has (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Domain-specific rationality in human choices: violations of utility axioms and social contexts.X. T. Wang - 1996 - Cognition 60 (1):31-63.
  • An experimental investigation of transitivity in set ranking.Amélie Vrijdags - 2010 - Theory and Decision 68 (1-2):213-232.
    A decision under ‘complete uncertainty’ is one where the decision maker knows the set of possible outcomes for each decision, but cannot assign probabilities to those outcomes. This way, the problem of ranking decisions is reduced to a problem of ranking sets of outcomes. All rankings that have emerged in the literature in this domain imply transitivity. In the current study, transitivity is subjected to an empirical evaluation in two experiments, where subjects are asked to choose between sets of monetary (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Not Having What You Want versus Having What You Do Not Want: The Impact of Type of Negative Outcome on the Experience of Disappointment and Related Emotions.Wilco W. van Dijk - 1999 - Cognition and Emotion 13 (2):129-148.
  • Decision Theory Without “Independence” or Without “Ordering”.Teddy Seidenfeld - 1988 - Economics and Philosophy 4 (2):267.
    It is a familiar argument that advocates accommodating the so-called paradoxes of decision theory by abandoning the “independence” postulate. After all, if we grant that choice reveals preference, the anomalous choice patterns of the Allais and Ellsberg problems violate postulate P2 of Savage's system. The strategy of making room for new preference patterns by relaxing independence is adopted in each of the following works: Samuelson, Kahneman and Tversky's “Prospect Theory”, Allais and Hagen, Fishburn, Chew and MacCrimmon, McClennen, and in closely (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • On experimental discourse in economics.Timo Tammi - 1999 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 29 (1):62-88.
    The devices with which experimental economists account for and justify their own and their opponents’ views are investigated by examining transcripts of interviews with two participants in experimental economics. The earlier investigations of natural scientists’ discourse provide material for comparisons. The results suggest that in assessing an opponent’s deviating view experimentalists in economics can be more cautious than natural scientists to characterize their opponents as influenced by personal and social factors. Indeed, they seem to admit that to some extent both (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Regret, recrimination and rationality.Robert Sugden - 1985 - Theory and Decision 19 (1):77-99.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Why humans are (sometimes) less rational than other animals: Cognitive complexity and the axioms of rational choice.Keith E. Stanovich - 2013 - Thinking and Reasoning 19 (1):1 - 26.
    (2013). Why humans are (sometimes) less rational than other animals: Cognitive complexity and the axioms of rational choice. Thinking & Reasoning: Vol. 19, No. 1, pp. 1-26. doi: 10.1080/13546783.2012.713178.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • A test of generalized expected utility theory.Barry Sopher & Gary Gigliotti - 1993 - Theory and Decision 35 (1):75-106.
  • Disappointment Aversion in internet Bidding-Decisions.Doron Sonsino - 2008 - Theory and Decision 64 (2-3):363-393.
    The article presents an Internet experiment where subjects sequentially bid for basic gifts and binary-lotteries on these gifts in incentive compatible Vickrey auctions. Subjects exhibit uniformly pessimistic prize-weighting in spite of precautions to reduce suspicion and prohibit collusion. The bids for lotteries are close to the minimal payable value, even when the probability of obtaining a better prize is larger than 50%. Prize-weighting becomes even more conservative as the distance in value of payable prizes increases. The twofold aversive affect appears (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A note on negativity bias and framing response asymmetry.Doron Sonsino - 2011 - Theory and Decision 71 (2):235-250.
    An unprocessed risk is a collection of simple lotteries with a reduction-rule that describes the actual-payoff to the decision-maker as a function of realized lottery outcomes. Experiments reveal that the willingness to pay for unprocessed risks is consistently biased toward the payoff-level in the unprocessed representation. The anchoring-to-frame bias in cases of positive framing is significantly weaker than in cases of negative framing suggesting that rational negativity bias may reflect in asymmetric violations of rationality.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Decision-making: from neuroscience to neuroeconomics—an overview.Daniel Serra - 2021 - Theory and Decision 91 (1):1-80.
    By the late 1990s, several converging trends in economics, psychology, and neuroscience had set the stage for the birth of a new scientific field known as “neuroeconomics”. Without the availability of an extensive variety of experimental designs for dealing with individual and social decision-making provided by experimental economics and psychology, many neuroeconomics studies could not have been developed. At the same time, without the significant progress made in neuroscience for grasping and understanding brain functioning, neuroeconomics would have never seen the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Rationality and uncertainty.Amartya Sen - 1985 - Theory and Decision 18 (2):109-127.
  • Subjective expected utility theory revisited: A reductio ad absurdum paradox.Paul J. H. Schoemaker - 1992 - Theory and Decision 33 (1):1-21.
  • Cognitive Models of Choice: Comparing Decision Field Theory to the Proportional Difference Model.Benjamin Scheibehenne, Jörg Rieskamp & Claudia González-Vallejo - 2009 - Cognitive Science 33 (5):911-939.
    People often face preferential decisions under risk. To further our understanding of the cognitive processes underlying these preferential choices, two prominent cognitive models, decision field theory (DFT; Busemeyer & Townsend, 1993) and the proportional difference model (PD; González‐Vallejo, 2002), were rigorously tested against each other. In two consecutive experiments, the participants repeatedly had to choose between monetary gambles. The first experiment provided the reference to estimate the models’ free parameters. From these estimations, new gamble pairs were generated for the second (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • An Experimental Investigation of the Disparity Between WTA and WTP for Lotteries.Ulrich Schmidt & Stefan Traub - 2009 - Theory and Decision 66 (3):229-262.
    In this paper we experimentally investigate the disparity between willingness-to-accept (WTA) and willingness-to-pay (WTP) for risky lotteries. The direction of the income effect is reversed by endowing subjects with the highest price of a lottery when asking the WTP question. Our results show that the income effect is too small to be the only source of the disparity. Since the disparity concentrates on a subsample of subjects, parametric and nonparametric tests of the WTA-WTP ratio may lead to contradictory results. The (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What are the benefits of preventive health care?Glenn Salkeld - 1998 - Health Care Analysis 6 (2):106-112.
    In most forms of evaluation the benefits of preventive health care are narrowly defined in terms of reductions in future morbidity and mortality. Thus it is normally assumed that it is the final health gains alone which bear utility. This discounts the possibility that individuals may derive utility from the process of health care and other outcomes as well as the end health states. Attributes such as anxiety, reassurance, autonomy, regret and hope provide potential benefits or disbenefits in addition to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A unified framework for addiction: Vulnerabilities in the decision process.A. David Redish, Steve Jensen & Adam Johnson - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (4):415-437.
    The understanding of decision-making systems has come together in recent years to form a unified theory of decision-making in the mammalian brain as arising from multiple, interacting systems (a planning system, a habit system, and a situation-recognition system). This unified decision-making system has multiple potential access points through which it can be driven to make maladaptive choices, particularly choices that entail seeking of certain drugs or behaviors. We identify 10 key vulnerabilities in the system: (1) moving away from homeostasis, (2) (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Addiction as vulnerabilities in the decision process.A. David Redish, Steve Jensen & Adam Johnson - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (4):461-487.
    In our target article, we proposed that addiction could be envisioned as misperformance of a decision-making machinery described by two systems (deliberative and habit systems). Several commentators have argued that Pavlovian learning also produces actions. We agree and note that Pavlovian action-selection will provide several additional vulnerabilities. Several commentators have suggested that addiction arises from sociological parameters. We note in our response how sociological effects can change decision-making variables to provide additional vulnerabilities. Commentators generally have agreed that our theory provides (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Towards a more precise decision framework.Robin Pope - 1995 - Theory and Decision 39 (3):241-265.
  • Deontic Reasoning With Emotional Content: Evolutionary Psychology or Decision Theory?Nick Perham & Mike Oaksford - 2005 - Cognitive Science 29 (5):681-718.
    Three experiments investigated the contrasting predictions of the evolutionary and decision-theoretic approaches to deontic reasoning. Two experiments embedded a hazard management (HM) rule in a social contract scenario that should lead to competition between innate modules. A 3rd experiment used a pure HM task. Threatening material was also introduced into the antecedent, p, of a deontic rule, if p then must q. According to the evolutionary approach, more HM responses (Cosmides & Tooby, 2000) are predicted when p is threatening, whereas (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • A paradox in decision theory and some experimental results: The relative nature of decisions.Iain Paterson & Andreas Diekmann - 1988 - Theory and Decision 25 (2):107-116.
  • Designing experiments informed by observational studies.Art B. Owen & Evan T. R. Rosenman - 2021 - Journal of Causal Inference 9 (1):147-171.
    The increasing availability of passively observed data has yielded a growing interest in “data fusion” methods, which involve merging data from observational and experimental sources to draw causal conclusions. Such methods often require a precarious tradeoff between the unknown bias in the observational dataset and the often-large variance in the experimental dataset. We propose an alternative approach, which avoids this tradeoff: rather than using observational data for inference, we use it to design a more efficient experiment. We consider the case (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Generalized Means Model for non-deterministic decision making: Its normative and descriptive power, including sketch of the representation theorem.Hector A. Munera - 1985 - Theory and Decision 18 (2):173-202.
  • Expected utility theory, Jeffrey’s decision theory, and the paradoxes.Philippe Mongin & Jean Baccelli - 2020 - Synthese 199 (1):695-713.
    In Richard Bradley’s book, Decision Theory with a Human Face, we have selected two themes for discussion. The first is the Bolker-Jeffrey theory of decision, which the book uses throughout as a tool to reorganize the whole field of decision theory, and in particular to evaluate the extent to which expected utility theories may be normatively too demanding. The second theme is the redefinition strategy that can be used to defend EU theories against the Allais and Ellsberg paradoxes, a strategy (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Alternative Omen Effect: Illusory negative correlation between the outcomes of choice options.Déborah Marciano-Romm, Assaf Romm, Sacha Bourgeois-Gironde & Leon Y. Deouell - 2016 - Cognition 146:324-338.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Regret Now, Compensate It Later: The Benefits of Experienced Regret on Future Altruism.Teng Lu, Dapeng Liang, Mei Hong & Jiayin Sun - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    This article explores how experienced regret and relief evoked in a risky gambling task influence subsequent intertemporal pro-social behavior. We apply a dictator game experiment with delayed rewards to investigate the effect on donating behavior by simultaneously the time delay when the recipient accepts the donation and the emotions experienced by the participant. We examine this effect using a choice titration procedure. The results reveal that independent of the prior experienced emotions, participants’ donations decrease as the time delay rises; the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Different experimental procedures for obtaining valuations of risky actions: Implications for utility theory. [REVIEW]Graham Loomes - 1988 - Theory and Decision 25 (1):1-23.
  • The role of regret in informed consent.Miles Little - 2008 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 6 (1):49-59.
    Informed consent to medical procedures tends to be construed in terms of principle-based ethics and one or other form of expected utility theory. These constructions leave problems created by imperfect communication; subjective distress and other emotions; imperfect knowledge and incomplete understanding; complexity, and previous experience or the lack of it. There is evidence that people giving consent to therapy or to research participation act intuitively and assess consequences holistically, being influenced more by the magnitude of outcomes than their probability. People (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • If nudge cannot be applied: a litmus test of the readers’ stance on paternalism. [REVIEW]Chen Li, Zhihua Li & Peter P. Wakker - 2014 - Theory and Decision 76 (3):297-315.
    A central question in many debates on paternalism is whether a decision analyst can ever go against the stated preference of a client, even if merely intending to improve the decisions for the client. Using four gedanken-experiments, this paper shows that this central question, so cleverly and aptly avoided by libertarian paternalism (nudge), cannot always be avoided. The four thought experiments, while purely hypothetical, serve to raise and specify the critical arguments in a maximally clear and pure manner. The first (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Equivalent decision trees and their associated strategy sets.Irving H. Lavalle & Peter C. Fishburn - 1987 - Theory and Decision 23 (1):37-63.
  • Comparing predicted and actual affective responses to process versus outcome: An emotion-as-feedback perspective.Jessica Yy Kwong, Kin Fai Ellick Wong & Suki Ky Tang - 2013 - Cognition 129 (1):42-50.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An opportunity cost model of subjective effort and task performance.Robert Kurzban, Angela Duckworth, Joseph W. Kable & Justus Myers - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (6):661-679.
    Why does performing certain tasks cause the aversive experience of mental effort and concomitant deterioration in task performance? One explanation posits a physical resource that is depleted over time. We propose an alternative explanation that centers on mental representations of the costs and benefits associated with task performance. Specifically, certain computational mechanisms, especially those associated with executive function, can be deployed for only a limited number of simultaneous tasks at any given moment. Consequently, the deployment of these computational mechanisms carries (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • Role of affective associations in the planning and habit systems of decision-making related to addiction.Marc T. Kiviniemi & Rick A. Bevins - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (4):450-451.
    The model proposed by Redish et al. considers vulnerabilities within decision systems based on expectancy-value assumptions. Further understanding of processes leading to addiction can be gained by considering other inputs to decision-making, particularly affective associations with behaviors. This consideration suggests additional decision-making vulnerabilities that might explain addictive behaviors.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intransitive choices based on transitive preferences: The case of menu-dependent information.Georg Kirchsteiger & Clemens Puppe - 1996 - Theory and Decision 41 (1):37-58.
  • Many heads are more utilitarian than one.Anita Keshmirian, Ophelia Deroy & Bahador Bahrami - 2022 - Cognition 220 (C):104965.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hold-up induced by demand for fairness: theory and experimental evidence.Raghabendra Pratap Kc, Dominique Olié Lauga & Vincent Mak - 2023 - Theory and Decision 94 (4):721-750.
    Research in recent years suggests that fairness concerns could mitigate hold-up problems. In this study, we report theoretical analysis and experimental evidence on an opposite possibility: that fairness concerns could also induce hold-up problems. In our setup, hold-up problems will not occur with purely self-interested agents, but theoretically could be induced by demand for distributional fairness among agents without sufficiently strong counteracting factors such as intention-based reciprocity. We observe a widespread occurrence of hold-up in our experiment. Relationship-specific investments occurred less (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sensitivity to Sunk Costs Depends on Attention to the Delay.Rebecca Kazinka, Angus W. MacDonald & A. David Redish - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    In the WebSurf task, humans forage for videos paying costs in terms of wait times on a time-limited task. A variant of the task in which demands during the wait time were manipulated revealed the role of attention in susceptibility to sunk costs. Consistent with parallel tasks in rodents, previous studies have found that humans preferred shorter delays, but waited longer for more preferred videos, suggesting that they were treating the delays economically. In an Amazon Mechanical Turk sample, we replicated (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Dynamic, Stochastic, Computational Model of Preference Reversal Phenomena.Joseph G. Johnson & Jerome R. Busemeyer - 2005 - Psychological Review 112 (4):841-861.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Probability Learning, Event-Splitting Effects and the Economic Theory of Choice.Steven J. Humphrey - 1999 - Theory and Decision 46 (1):51-78.
    This paper reports an experiment which investigates a possible cognitive antecedent of event-splitting effects (ESEs) experimentally observed by Starmer and Sugden (1993) and Humphrey (1995) – the learning of absolute frequency of event category impacting on the learning of probability of event category – and reveals some evidence that it is responsible for observed ESEs. It is also suggested and empirically substantiated that stripped-down prospect theory will accurately predict ESEs in some decision making tasks, but will not perform well in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Expected utility versus expected regret theory versions of decision curve analysis do generate different results when treatment effects are taken into account.Iztok Hozo, Athanasios Tsalatsanis & Benjamin Djulbegovic - 2018 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 24 (1):65-71.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Dynamic Choice, Independence and Emotions.Astrid Hopfensitz & Frans Van Winden - 2008 - Theory and Decision 64 (2-3):249-300.
    From the viewpoint of the independence axiom of expected utility theory, an interesting empirical dynamic choice problem involves the presence of a “global risk,” that is, a chance of losing everything whichever safe or risky option is chosen. In this experimental study, participants have to allocate real money between a safe and a risky project. Treatment variable is the particular decision stage at which a global risk is resolved: (i) before the investment decision; (ii) after the investment decision, but before (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation