Switch to: References

Citations of:

A course in mathematical logic

New York: sole distributors for the U.S.A. and Canada American Elsevier Pub. Co.. Edited by Moshé Machover (1977)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A Set of Axioms for Neoclassical Economics and the Methodological Status of the Equilibrium Concept.Arnis Vilks - 1992 - Economics and Philosophy 8 (1):51-82.
    It is widely agreed that the concept of general equilibrium and, in particular, general equilibrium existence proofs play a central role within the neoclassical approach to economic theory. There is much less agreement, however, on the concepts of general equilibrium and of neoclassical economic theory themselves.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Quasi-lattice of Indiscernible Elements.Mauri Cunha do Nascimento, Décio Krause & Hércules Araújo Feitosa - 2011 - Studia Logica 97 (1):101-126.
    The literature on quantum logic emphasizes that the algebraic structures involved with orthodox quantum mechanics are non distributive. In this paper we develop a particular algebraic structure, the quasi-lattice ( $${\mathfrak{I}}$$ -lattice), which can be modeled by an algebraic structure built in quasi-set theory $${\mathfrak{Q}}$$. This structure is non distributive and involve indiscernible elements. Thus we show that in taking into account indiscernibility as a primitive concept, the quasi-lattice that ‘naturally’ arises is non distributive.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Consistency, mechanicalness, and the logic of the mind.Qiuen Yu - 1992 - Synthese 90 (1):145-79.
    G. Priest's anti-consistency argument (Priest 1979, 1984, 1987) and J. R. Lucas's anti-mechanist argument (Lucas 1961, 1968, 1970, 1984) both appeal to Gödel incompleteness. By way of refuting them, this paper defends the thesis of quartet compatibility, viz., that the logic of the mind can simultaneously be Gödel incomplete, consistent, mechanical, and recursion complete (capable of all means of recursion). A representational approach is pursued, which owes its origin to works by, among others, J. Myhill (1964), P. Benacerraf (1967), J. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Propositions and compositionality.Juhani Yli-Vakkuri - 2013 - Philosophical Perspectives 27 (1):526-563.
  • Embeddability, syntax, and semantics in accounts of scientific theories.Peter Turney - 1990 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 19 (4):429 - 451.
    Recently several philosophers of science have proposed what has come to be known as the semantic account of scientific theories. It is presented as an improvement on the positivist account, which is now called the syntactic account of scientific theories. Bas van Fraassen claims that the syntactic account does not give a satisfactory definition of "empirical adequacy" and "empirical equivalence". He contends that his own semantic account does define these notations acceptably, through the concept of "embeddability", a concept which he (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Minimal logic is adequate for Popperian science.Neil Tennant - 1985 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (3):325-329.
  • How far can Hume's is-ought thesis be generalized?Gerhard Schurz - 1991 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 20 (1):37 - 95.
  • Divergent Mathematical Treatments in Utility Theory.Davide Rizza - 2016 - Erkenntnis 81 (6):1287-1303.
    In this paper I study how divergent mathematical treatments affect mathematical modelling, with a special focus on utility theory. In particular I examine recent work on the ranking of information states and the discounting of future utilities, in order to show how, by replacing the standard analytical treatment of the models involved with one based on the framework of Nonstandard Analysis, diametrically opposite results are obtained. In both cases, the choice between the standard and nonstandard treatment amounts to a selection (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Axiomatising first-order temporal logic: Until and since over linear time.Mark Reynolds - 1996 - Studia Logica 57 (2-3):279 - 302.
    We present an axiomatisation for the first-order temporal logic with connectives Until and Since over the class of all linear flows of time. Completeness of the axiom system is proved.We also add a few axioms to find a sound and complete axiomatisation for the first order temporal logic of Until and Since over rational numbers time.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Quantified modal logic: Non-normal worlds and propositional attitudes.Veikko Rantala - 1982 - Studia Logica 41 (1):41 - 65.
    One way to obtain a comprehensive semantics for various systems of modal logic is to use a general notion of non-normal world. In the present article, a general notion of modal system is considered together with a semantic framework provided by such a general notion of non-normal world. Methodologically, the main purpose of this paper is to provide a logical framework for the study of various modalities, notably prepositional attitudes. Some specific systems are studied together with semantics using non-normal worlds (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • The concept of truth in a finite universe.Panu Raatikainen - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (6):617-633.
    The prospects and limitations of defining truth in a finite model in the same language whose truth one is considering are thoroughly examined. It is shown that in contradistinction to Tarski's undefinability theorem for arithmetic, it is in a definite sense possible in this case to define truth in the very language whose truth is in question.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Correspondence as an intertheory relation.David Pearce & Veikko Rantala - 1983 - Studia Logica 42 (2-3):363 - 371.
    In this paper we give the gist of our reconstructed notion of (limiting case) correspondence. Our notion is very general, so that it should be applicable to all the cases in which a correspondence has been said to exist in actual science.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A logical study of the correspondence relation.David Pearce & Veikko Rantala - 1984 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 13 (1):47 - 84.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Temporal Algebras, Pretemporal Algebras, and Modal Algebras: A Relation between Time and Necessity.Francisco M. García Olmedo & Antonio J. Rodríguez Salas - 1995 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 41 (1):24-38.
    In this paper the structure of pretemporal algebra is used to study some aspects of temporal algebras and modal algebras. The paper contains a computational approach to finite temporal algebras and a general splitting theorem for finite temporal algebras.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Gödel Sentences and What They Say.Peter Milne - 2007 - Philosophia Mathematica 15 (2):193-226.
    Proofs of Gödel's First Incompleteness Theorem are often accompanied by claims such as that the gödel sentence constructed in the course of the proof says of itself that it is unprovable and that it is true. The validity of such claims depends closely on how the sentence is constructed. Only by tightly constraining the means of construction can one obtain gödel sentences of which it is correct, without further ado, to say that they say of themselves that they are unprovable (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Bruno de finetti and the logic of conditional events.Peter Milne - 1997 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (2):195-232.
    This article begins by outlining some of the history—beginning with brief remarks of Quine's—of work on conditional assertions and conditional events. The upshot of the historical narrative is that diverse works from various starting points have circled around a nexus of ideas without convincingly tying them together. Section 3 shows how ideas contained in a neglected article of de Finetti's lead to a unified treatment of the topics based on the identification of conditional events as the objects of conditional bets. (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • The place of nonstandard analysis in mathematics and in mathematics teaching.Moshé Machover - 1993 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (2):205-212.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Empirical Adequacy in the Received View.Sebastian Lutz - 2014 - Philosophy of Science 81 (5):1171-1183.
    I show that the central notion of Constructive Empiricism, empirical adequacy, can be expressed syntactically and specifically in the Received View of the logical empiricists. The formalization shows that the Received View is superior to Constructive Empiricism in the treatment of theories involving constants or functions from observable to unobservable objects. It also suggests a formalization of ‘full empirical informativeness’ in Constructive Empiricism.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Towards a classification of defaults logics.Thomas Link & Torsten Schaub - 1997 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 7 (4):397-451.
    ABSTRACT Reiter's default logic is one of the most prominent and well-studied approaches to nonmonotonic reasoning. Its evolution has resulted in diverse variants enjoying many interesting properties. This process however seems to be diverging because it has led to default logics that are difficult to compare due to different formal characterizations—sometimes even dealing with different objects of discourse. This problem is addressed in this paper in two ways. One the one hand, we elaborate on the relationships between different types of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reviews. [REVIEW]Noretta Koertge - 1978 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (2):204-207.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can a many-valued language functionally represent its own semantics?Jeffrey Ketland - 2003 - Analysis 63 (4):292–297.
    Tarski’s Indefinability Theorem can be generalized so that it applies to many-valued languages. We introduce a notion of strong semantic self-representation applicable to any (sufficiently rich) interpreted many-valued language L. A sufficiently rich interpreted many-valued language L is SSSR just in case it has a function symbol n(x) such that, for any f Sent(L), the denotation of the term n(“f”) in L is precisely ||f||L, the semantic value of f in L. By a simple diagonal construction (finding a sentence l (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Tools, Objects, and Chimeras: Connes on the Role of Hyperreals in Mathematics.Vladimir Kanovei, Mikhail G. Katz & Thomas Mormann - 2013 - Foundations of Science 18 (2):259-296.
    We examine some of Connes’ criticisms of Robinson’s infinitesimals starting in 1995. Connes sought to exploit the Solovay model S as ammunition against non-standard analysis, but the model tends to boomerang, undercutting Connes’ own earlier work in functional analysis. Connes described the hyperreals as both a “virtual theory” and a “chimera”, yet acknowledged that his argument relies on the transfer principle. We analyze Connes’ “dart-throwing” thought experiment, but reach an opposite conclusion. In S , all definable sets of reals are (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Putnam's indeterminacy argument: The skolemization of absolutely everything.Carsten Hansen - 1987 - Philosophical Studies 51 (1):77--99.
  • The Development of Mathematics. [REVIEW]Donald Gillies - 1978 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (1):68-87.
  • Lessons from the History and Philosophy of Science regarding the Research Assessment Exercise.Donald Gillies - 2007 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 61:37-73.
    The Research Assessment Exercise was introduced in 1986 by Thatcher, and was continued by Blair. So it has now been running for 21 years. During this time, the rules governing the RAE have changed considerably, and the interval between successive RAEs has also varied. These changes are not of great importance as far as the argument of this paper is concerned. We will concentrate on the main features of the RAE which can be summarised as follows.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reinflating the semantic approach.Steven French & James Ladyman - 1999 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 13 (2):103 – 121.
    The semantic, or model-theoretic, approach to theories has recently come under criticism on two fronts: (i) it is claimed that it cannot account for the wide diversity of models employed in scientific practice—a claim which has led some to propose a “deflationary” account of models; (ii) it is further contended that the sense of “model” used by the approach differs from that given in model theory. Our aim in the present work is to articulate a possible response to these claims, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   140 citations  
  • Logic TK: Algebraic Notions from Tarski’s Consequence Operator.Hércules A. Feitosa, Mauri C. Do Nascimento & Maria Claudia C. Grácio - 2010 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 14 (1):47-70.
    Tarski apresentou sua definição de operador de consequência com a intenção de expor as concepções fundamentais da consequência lógica. Um espaço de Tarski é um par ordenado determinado por um conjunto não vazio e um operador de consequência sobre este conjunto. Esta estrutura matemática caracteriza um espaço quase topológico. Este artigo mostra uma visão algébrica dos espaços de Tarski e introduz uma lógica proposicional modal que interpreta o seu operador modal nos conjuntos fechados de algum espaço de Tarski. DOI:10.5007/1808-1711.2010v14n1p47.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Models for stronger normal intuitionistic modal logics.Kosta Došen - 1985 - Studia Logica 44 (1):39 - 70.
    This paper, a sequel to Models for normal intuitionistic modal logics by M. Boi and the author, which dealt with intuitionistic analogues of the modal system K, deals similarly with intuitionistic analogues of systems stronger than K, and, in particular, analogues of S4 and S5. For these prepositional logics Kripke-style models with two accessibility relations, one intuitionistic and the other modal, are given, and soundness and completeness are proved with respect to these models. It is shown how the holding of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Tarski on “essentially richer” metalanguages.David DeVidi & Graham Solomon - 1999 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 28 (1):1-28.
    It is well known that Tarski proved a result which can be stated roughly as: no sufficiently rich, consistent, classical language can contain its own truth definition. Tarski's way around this problem is to deal with two languages at a time, an object language for which we are defining truth and a metalanguage in which the definition occurs. An obvious question then is: under what conditions can we construct a definition of truth for a given object language. Tarski claims that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Intuitionistic ε- and τ-calculi.David Devidi - 1995 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 41 (4):523-546.
    There are several open problems in the study of the calculi which result from adding either of Hilbert's ϵ- or τ-operators to the first order intuitionistic predicate calculus. This paper provides answers to several of them. In particular, the first complete and sound semantics for these calculi are presented, in both a “quasi-extensional” version which uses choice functions in a straightforward way to interpret the ϵ- or τ-terms, and in a form which does not require extensionality assumptions. Unlike the classical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Elementary propositions and essentially incomplete knowledge: A framework for the interpretation of quantum mechanics.William Demopoulos - 2004 - Noûs 38 (1):86–109.
    A central problem in the interpretation of non-relativistic quantum mechanics is to relate the conceptual structure of the theory to the classical idea of the state of a physical system. This paper approaches the problem by presenting an analysis of the notion of an elementary physical proposition. The notion is shown to be realized in standard formulations of the theory and to illuminate the significance of proofs of the impossibility of hidden variable extensions. In the interpretation of quantum mechanics that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On some formalized conservation results in arithmetic.P. Clote, P. Hájek & J. Paris - 1990 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 30 (4):201-218.
    IΣ n andBΣ n are well known fragments of first-order arithmetic with induction and collection forΣ n formulas respectively;IΣ n 0 andBΣ n 0 are their second-order counterparts. RCA0 is the well known fragment of second-order arithmetic with recursive comprehension;WKL 0 isRCA 0 plus weak König's lemma. We first strengthen Harrington's conservation result by showing thatWKL 0 +BΣ n 0 is Π 1 1 -conservative overRCA 0 +BΣ n 0 . Then we develop some model theory inWKL 0 and illustrate (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A logical expression of reasoning.Arthur Buchsbaum, Tarcisio Pequeno & Marcelino Pequeno - 2007 - Synthese 154 (3):431 - 466.
    A non-monotonic logic, the Logic of Plausible Reasoning (LPR), capable of coping with the demands of what we call complex reasoning, is introduced. It is argued that creative complex reasoning is the way of reasoning required in many instances of scientific thought, professional practice and common life decision taking. For managing the simultaneous consideration of multiple scenarios inherent in these activities, two new modalities, weak and strong plausibility, are introduced as part of the Logic of Plausible Deduction (LPD), a deductive (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The world, the flesh and the argument from design.William Boos - 1994 - Synthese 101 (1):15 - 52.
    In the the passage just quoted from theDialogues concerning Natural Religion, David Hume developed a thought-experiment that contravened his better-known views about chance expressed in hisTreatise and firstEnquiry.For among other consequences of the eternal-recurrence hypothesis Philo proposes in this passage, it may turn out that what the vulgar call cause is nothing but a secret and concealed chance.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The world, the flesh and the argument from design.William Boos - 1995 - Synthese 104 (2):15 - 52.
    In the the passage just quoted from the Dialogues concerning Natural Religion, David Hume developed a thought-experiment that contravened his better-known views about "chance" expressed in his Treatise and first Enquiry. For among other consequences of the 'eternal-recurrence' hypothesis Philo proposes in this passage, it may turn out that what the vulgar call cause is nothing but a secret and concealed chance. (In this sentence, I have simply reversed "cause" and "chance" in a well-known passage from Hume's Treatise, p. 130). (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mathematical quantum theory I: Random ultrafilters as hidden variables.William Boos - 1996 - Synthese 107 (1):83 - 143.
    The basic purpose of this essay, the first of an intended pair, is to interpret standard von Neumann quantum theory in a framework of iterated measure algebraic truth for mathematical (and thus mathematical-physical) assertions — a framework, that is, in which the truth-values for such assertions are elements of iterated boolean measure-algebras (cf. Sections 2.2.9, 5.2.1–5.2.6 and 5.3 below).The essay itself employs constructions of Takeuti's boolean-valued analysis (whose origins lay in work of Scott, Solovay, Krauss and others) to provide a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Models for normal intuitionistic modal logics.Milan Božić & Kosta Došen - 1984 - Studia Logica 43 (3):217 - 245.
    Kripke-style models with two accessibility relations, one intuitionistic and the other modal, are given for analogues of the modal systemK based on Heyting's prepositional logic. It is shown that these two relations can combine with each other in various ways. Soundness and completeness are proved for systems with only the necessity operator, or only the possibility operator, or both. Embeddings in modal systems with several modal operators, based on classical propositional logic, are also considered. This paper lays the ground for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Whole and part in mathematics.John L. Bell - 2004 - Axiomathes 14 (4):285-294.
    The centrality of the whole/part relation in mathematics is demonstrated through the presentation and analysis of examples from algebra, geometry, functional analysis,logic, topology and category theory.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Incompleteness in a general setting.John L. Bell - 2007 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 13 (1):21-30.
    Full proofs of the Gödel incompleteness theorems are highly intricate affairs. Much of the intricacy lies in the details of setting up and checking the properties of a coding system representing the syntax of an object language within that same language. These details are seldom illuminating and tend to obscure the core of the argument. For this reason a number of efforts have been made to present the essentials of the proofs of Gödel's theorems without getting mired in syntactic or (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • From absolute to local mathematics.J. L. Bell - 1986 - Synthese 69 (3):409 - 426.
    In this paper (a sequel to [4]) I put forward a "local" interpretation of mathematical concepts based on notions derived from category theory. The fundamental idea is to abandon the unique absolute universe of sets central to the orthodox set-theoretic account of the foundations of mathematics, replacing it by a plurality of local mathematical frameworks - elementary toposes - defined in category-theoretic terms.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • A theory of sets with the negation of the axiom of infinity.Stefano Baratella & Ruggero Ferro - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):338-352.
    In this paper we introduce a theory of finite sets FST with a strong negation of the axiom of infinity asserting that every set is provably bijective with a natural number. We study in detail the role of the axioms of Power Set, Choice, Regularity in FST, pointing out the relative dependences or independences among them. FST is shown to be provably equivalent to a fragment of Alternative Set Theory. Furthermore, the introduction of FST is motivated in view of a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A universal scale of comparison.Alan Clinton Bale - 2008 - Linguistics and Philosophy 31 (1):1-55.
    Comparative constructions form two classes, those that permit direct comparisons (comparisons of measurements as in Seymour is taller than he is wide) and those that only allow indirect comparisons (comparisons of relative positions on separate scales as in Esme is more beautiful than Einstein is intelligent). In contrast with other semantic theories, this paper proposes that the interpretation of the comparative morpheme remains the same whether it appears in sentences that compare individuals directly or indirectly. To develop a unified account, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Jean van Heijenoort’s Contributions to Proof Theory and Its History.Irving H. Anellis - 2012 - Logica Universalis 6 (3-4):411-458.
    Jean van Heijenoort was best known for his editorial work in the history of mathematical logic. I survey his contributions to model-theoretic proof theory, and in particular to the falsifiability tree method. This work of van Heijenoort’s is not widely known, and much of it remains unpublished. A complete list of van Heijenoort’s unpublished writings on tableaux methods and related work in proof theory is appended.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Editor’s Introduction to Jean van Heijenoort, Historical Development of Modern Logic.Irving H. Anellis - 2012 - Logica Universalis 6 (3-4):301-326.
    Van Heijenoort’s account of the historical development of modern logic was composed in 1974 and first published in 1992 with an introduction by his former student. What follows is a new edition with a revised and expanded introduction and additional notes.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Computer science temporal logics need their clocks.Ildikó Sain - 1989 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 18 (4):153-160.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark