Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Contextual and psychometric descriptions of intelligence: A fundamental conflict.Barry J. Zimmerman - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):303.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A triarchic reaction to a triarchic theory of intelligence.Steven R. Yussen - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):303.
  • Well-being, categorical deprivation and pleasure.Yossi Yonah - 2001 - Philosophia 28 (1-4):233-253.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Well-being, categorical deprivation and the role of education.Yossi Yonah - 1994 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 28 (2):191–204.
    ABSTRACT“How should a person lead her life?” The purpose of this paper is to suggest some principles (not a complete list) which will serve us ‘intellectual instruments’ for assessing forms of life. These principles are utilitarian in nature, and, as I will argue, essential to a reasonably rich account of personal well-being. The principles suggested are not instrumental, that is, they determine the worthiness of a form of life led by an agent irrespective of whether it satisfies her existing desires (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Well-being, Categorical Deprivation and the Role of Education.Yossi Yonah - 1994 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 28 (2):191-204.
    “How should a person lead her life?” The purpose of this paper is to suggest some principles (not a complete list) which will serve us ‘intellectual instruments’ for assessing forms of life. These principles are utilitarian in nature, and, as I will argue, essential to a reasonably rich account of personal well-being. The principles suggested are not instrumental, that is, they determine the worthiness of a form of life led by an agent irrespective of whether it satisfies her existing desires (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Jensen's support for Spearman's hypothesis is support for a circular argument.James R. Wilson - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):246-246.
  • Focusing on trainable g.Arthur Whimbey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):245-246.
  • Intelligence: Some neglected topics.Philip E. Vernon - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):302.
  • Interpretation of black–white differences in g.Philip E. Vernon - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):244-245.
  • Some possible implications of Sternberg's triarchic theory of intelligence.Leona E. Tyler - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):301-302.
  • Speed and adaptivity in intelligence.Harry C. Triandis - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):301-301.
  • The consequences of taking consequentialism seriously.Philip E. Tetlock - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):31-32.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Actions, inactions and the temporal dimension.Karl Halvor Teigen - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):30-31.
  • Moral heuristics.Cass R. Sunstein - 2005 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (4):531-542.
    With respect to questions of fact, people use heuristics – mental short-cuts, or rules of thumb, that generally work well, but that also lead to systematic errors. People use moral heuristics too – moral short-cuts, or rules of thumb, that lead to mistaken and even absurd moral judgments. These judgments are highly relevant not only to morality, but to law and politics as well. Examples are given from a number of domains, including risk regulation, punishment, reproduction and sexuality, and the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   140 citations  
  • The black–white differences and Spearman's g: Old wine in new bottles that still doesn't taste good.Robert J. Sternberg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):244-244.
  • Toward a triarchic theory of human intelligence.Robert J. Sternberg - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):269-287.
    This article is a synopsis of a triarchic theory of human intelligence. The theory comprises three subtheories: a contextual subtheory, which relates intelligence to the external world of the individual; a componential subtheory, which relates intelligence to the individual's internal world; and a two-facet subtheory, which relates intelligence to both the external and internal worlds. The contextual subtheory defines intelligent behavior in terms of purposive adaptation to, shaping of, and selection of real-world environments relevant to one's life. The normal course (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • If at first you don't believe, try “tri” again Contextual and psychometric descriptions of intelligence: A fundamental conflict.Robert J. Sternberg - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):304.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The black–white differences are real: Where do we go from here?Keith E. Stanovich - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):242-243.
  • Advancing the rationality debate.Keith E. Stanovich & Richard F. West - 2000 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23 (5):701-717.
    In this response, we clarify several misunderstandings of the understanding/acceptance principle and defend our specific operationalization of that principle. We reiterate the importance of addressing the problem of rational task construal and we elaborate the notion of computational limitations contained in our target article. Our concept of thinking dispositions as variable intentional-level styles of epistemic and behavioral regulation is explained, as is its relation to the rationality debate. Many of the suggestions of the commentators for elaborating two-process models are easily (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • What goals are to count?Mark D. Spranca - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):29-30.
  • On artificial intelligence.Peter H. Schönemann - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):241-242.
  • Neural adaptability: A biological determinant of g factor intelligence.Edward W. P. Schafer - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):240-241.
  • Goals, values and benefits.Frederic Schick - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):29-29.
  • Cognitive Adaptation: Insights from a Pragmatist Perspective.Jay Schulkin - 2008 - Contemporary Pragmatism 5 (1):39-59.
    Classical pragmatism construed mind as an adaptive organ rooted in biology; biology was not one side and culture on the other. The cognitive systems underlie adaptation in response to the precarious and in the search for the stable and more secure that result in diverse forms of inquiry. Cognitive systems are rooted in action, and classical pragmatism knotted our sense of ourselves in response to nature and our cultural evolution. Cognitive systems should be demythologized away from Cartesian detachment, and towards (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Differential K theory and group differences in intelligence.J. Philippe Rushton - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):239-240.
  • Are Thoughtful People More Utilitarian? CRT as a Unique Predictor of Moral Minimalism in the Dilemmatic Context.Edward B. Royzman, Justin F. Landy & Robert F. Leeman - 2015 - Cognitive Science 39 (2):325-352.
    Recent theorizing about the cognitive underpinnings of dilemmatic moral judgment has equated slow, deliberative thinking with the utilitarian disposition and fast, automatic thinking with the deontological disposition. However, evidence for the reflective utilitarian hypothesis—the hypothesized link between utilitarian judgment and individual differences in the capacity for rational reflection has been inconsistent and difficult to interpret in light of several design flaws. In two studies aimed at addressing some of the flaws, we found robust evidence for a reflective minimalist hypothesis—high CRT (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • What are the interrelations among the three subtheories of Sternberg's triarchic theory of intelligence?Barbara Rogoff - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):300-301.
  • Can goals be uniquely defined?Ilana Ritov - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):28-29.
  • Intelligence, adaptation, and inverted selection.Marc N. Richelle - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):299-300.
  • Broadening the base for bringing cognitive psychology to bear on ethics.Peter Railton - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):27-28.
  • Oh g Dr. Jensen! or, g-ing up cognitive psychology?P. M. A. Rabbitt - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):238-239.
  • How intelligent can one be?Kjell Raaheim - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):298-298.
  • Chronometric measures of g.Michael I. Posner - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):237-238.
  • Empirical evidence of bias in choice reaction time experiments.Ype H. Poortinga - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):236-237.
  • A “should” too many.Paul M. Pietroski - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):26-27.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some examples of nonconsequentialist decisions.Gerald M. Phillips - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):25-26.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Context and novelty in an integrated theory of intelligence.James W. Pellegrino & Susan R. Goldman - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):297-298.
  • In what sense does intelligence underlie an intelligent performance?David R. Olson - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):296-297.
  • Side effects: Limitations of human rationality.Keith Oatley - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):24-25.
  • Précis of bayesian rationality: The probabilistic approach to human reasoning.Mike Oaksford & Nick Chater - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (1):69-84.
    According to Aristotle, humans are the rational animal. The borderline between rationality and irrationality is fundamental to many aspects of human life including the law, mental health, and language interpretation. But what is it to be rational? One answer, deeply embedded in the Western intellectual tradition since ancient Greece, is that rationality concerns reasoning according to the rules of logic – the formal theory that specifies the inferential connections that hold with certainty between propositions. Piaget viewed logical reasoning as defining (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Intelligence and its biological subtrate.Robert C. Nichols - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):236-236.
  • What reaction times time.T. Nettelbeck - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):235-235.
  • Naïve optimality: Subjects' heuristics can be better motivated than experimenters' optimal models.Jonathan D. Nelson - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (1):94-95.
    Is human cognition best described by optimal models, or by adaptive but suboptimal heuristic strategies? It is frequently hard to identify which theoretical model is normatively best justified. In the context of information search, naoptimal” models.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Finding Useful Questions: On Bayesian Diagnosticity, Probability, Impact, and Information Gain.Jonathan D. Nelson - 2005 - Psychological Review 112 (4):979-999.
  • Does consequentialism pay?Adam Morton - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):24-24.
  • Consequentialism in haste.Roger A. McCain - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):23-24.
  • Comparative studies of animal intelligence: Is Spearman's g really Hull's D?Euan M. Macphail - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):234-235.
  • Jonathan Baron, consequentialism and error theory.Sanford S. Levy - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):22-23.
  • The nature of psychometric g.Paul Kline - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):234-234.
  • : A dual-process approach to cognitive development: The case of children's understanding of sunk cost decisions.Paul A. Klaczynski & Jennifer M. Cottrell - 2004 - Thinking and Reasoning 10 (2):147 – 174.
    Only in recent years have developmental psychologists begun advocating and exploring dual-process theories and their applicability to cognitive development. In this paper, a dual-process model of developments in two processing systems—an “analytic” and an “experiential” system—is discussed. We emphasise the importance of “metacognitive intercession” and developments in this ability to override experiential processing. In each of two studies of sunk cost decisions, age-related developments in normative decisions were observed, as were declines in the use of a “waste not” heuristic. In (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations