Switch to: References

Citations of:

Interpretations of quantifiers

Mind 88 (350):215-240 (1979)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A Chrysippean Modality.D. T. J. Bailey - forthcoming - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie.
    In this paper, I attempt to explain one of the most controversial views attributed to the Stoic Chrysippus: that the impossible can follow from the possible. My solution finds in Chrysippus a distinction later made by the medieval logician John Buridan: that between being possible (there being a state of affairs that may occur) and being possibly-true (there being some proposition whose truth-conditions are that state of affairs). Buridan and Chrysippus have radically opposing views on the nature of propositions. What (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The logical form of categorical sentences.Alex Orenstein - 2000 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (4):517 – 533.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Quantification and ontology.Shaughan Lavine - 2000 - Synthese 124 (1-2):1-43.
    Quineans have taken the basic expression of ontological commitment to be an assertion of the form '' x '', assimilated to theEnglish ''there is something that is a ''. Here I take the existential quantifier to be introduced, not as an abbreviation for an expression of English, but via Tarskian semantics. I argue, contrary to the standard view, that Tarskian semantics in fact suggests a quite different picture: one in which quantification is of a substitutional type apparently first proposed by (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The functions of Russell’s no class theory.Kevin C. Klement - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (4):633-664.
    Certain commentators on Russell's “no class” theory, in which apparent reference to classes or sets is eliminated using higher-order quantification, including W. V. Quine and (recently) Scott Soames, have doubted its success, noting the obscurity of Russell’s understanding of so-called “propositional functions”. These critics allege that realist readings of propositional functions fail to avoid commitment to classes or sets (or something equally problematic), and that nominalist readings fail to meet the demands placed on classes by mathematics. I show that Russell (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Reconciling Aristotle and Frege.Alex Orenstein - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (3):391-413.
    An account of Aristotle's syllogistic (including a full square of opposition and allowing for empty nouns) as an integral part of first-order predicate logic is lacking. Some say it is not possible. It is not found in the tradition stemming from ukasiewicz's attempt nor in less formal approaches such as Strawson's. The ukasiewicz tradition leaves Aristotle's syllogistic as an autonomous axiomatized system. In this paper Aristotle's syllogistic is presented within first-order predicate logic with special restricted quantifiers. The theory is not (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Proof Theory and Meaning.B. G. Sundholm - unknown
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations