Switch to: References

Citations of:

In defense of passive

Linguistics and Philosophy 3 (3):297 - 341 (1979)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Boolean Semantics for Natural Language.Edward Louis Keenan & L. M. Faltz - 1984 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    In the spring of 1978, one of the authors of this book was sitting in on a course in logic for linguists given by the other author. In attempting to present some of Montague's insights in an elementary way, the authors began dis cussions aimed towards the construction of a simple model-theoretical semantic apparatus which could be applied directly to a small English-like language and used to illustrate the methods of formal logical interpretation. In these discussions two points impressed themselves (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • NP trace in Theta theory.Edwin Williams - 1987 - Linguistics and Philosophy 10 (4):433 - 447.
  • Transitividad e impersonalidad gramatical en la Antigüedad grecolatina.Mª Victoria Manzano Ventura - 2010 - Humanitas 62:83-112.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • LFG and psychological explanation.Mark Steedman - 1985 - Linguistics and Philosophy 8 (3):359 - 385.
  • Two theories of syntactic categories.Susan F. Schmerling - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (3):393 - 421.
  • A functional analysis of pseudo-passives.Elizabeth Riddle & Gloria Sheintuch - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (4):527 - 563.
  • The (Dis)organization of the Grammar: 25 Years.Jacobson Pauline - 2002 - Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (5-6):601-626.
  • Formal Semantics: Origins, Issues, Early Impact.Barbara H. Partee - 2010 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6 (1).
    Formal semantics is an approach to SEMANTICS1, the study of meaning, with roots in logic, the philosophy of language, and linguistics, and since the 1980’s a core area of linguistic theory. Characteristics of formal semantics to be treated in this article include the following: Formal semanticists treat meaning as mind-independent (though abstract), contrasting with the view of meanings as concepts “in the head” (see I-LANGUAGE AND E-LANGUAGE and MEANING EXTERNALISM AND INTERNALISM); formal semanticists distinguish semantics from knowledge of semantics (Lewis (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Formal Semantics: Origins, Issues, Early Impact.Barbara H. Partee - 2011 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6:13.
    Formal semantics and pragmatics as they have developed since the late 1960's have been shaped by fruitful interdisciplinary collaboration among linguists, philosophers, and logicians, among others, and in turn have had noticeable effects on developments in syntax, philosophy of language, computational linguistics, and cognitive science.In this paper I describe the environment in which formal semantics was born and took root, highlighting the differences in ways of thinking about natural language semantics in linguistics and in philosophy and logic. With Montague as (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Discontinuity in categorial grammar.Glyn Morrill - 1995 - Linguistics and Philosophy 18 (2):175 - 219.
    Discontinuity refers to the character of many natural language constructions wherein signs differ markedly in their prosodic and semantic forms. As such it presents interesting demands on monostratal computational formalisms which aspire to descriptive adequacy. Pied piping, in particular, is argued by Pollard (1988) to motivate phrase structure-style feature percolation. In the context of categorial grammar, Bach (1981, 1984), Moortgat (1988, 1990, 1991) and others have sought to provide categorial operators suited to discontinuity. These attempts encounter certain difficulties with respect (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Type-driven translation.Ewan Klein & Ivan A. Sag - 1985 - Linguistics and Philosophy 8 (2):163 - 201.
  • The (dis)organization of the grammar: 25 years. [REVIEW]Pauline Jacobson - 2002 - Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (5-6):601-626.
  • Raising as function composition.Pauline Jacobson - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (4):423 - 475.
  • Paycheck Pronouns, Bach-Peters Sentences, and Variable-Free Semantics.Pauline Jacobson - 2000 - Natural Language Semantics 8 (2):77-155.
    This paper argues for the hypothesis of direct compositionality (as in, e.g., Montague 1974), according to which the combinatory syntactic rules specify a set of well-formed expressions while the semantic combinatory rules work in tandem to directly supply a model-theoretic interpretation to each expression as it is "built" in the syntax. (This thus obviates the need for any level like LF and, concomitantly, for any rules mapping surface structures to such a level.) I focus here on one related group of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Complex predicates and liberation in dutch and English.Jack Hoeksema - 1991 - Linguistics and Philosophy 14 (6):661 - 710.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Generalized phrase structure grammar and japanese reflexivization.Takao Gunji - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (1):115 - 156.
  • On recent analyses of the semantics of control.David R. Dowty - 1985 - Linguistics and Philosophy 8 (3):291 - 331.
  • Semantics and property theory.Gennaro Chierchia & Raymond Turner - 1988 - Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (3):261 - 302.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Nominalization and Montague grammar: A semantics without types for natural languages.Gennaro Chierchia - 1982 - Linguistics and Philosophy 5 (3):303 - 354.
    We started from the fact that type theory, in the way it was implemented in IL, makes it costly to deal with nominalization processes. We have also argued that the type hierarchy as such doesn't play any real role in a grammar; the classification it provides for different semantic objects is already contained, in some sense, in the categorial structure of the grammar itself. So, on the basis of a theory of properties (Cocchiarella's HST*) we have tried to build a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 9.Emar Maier, Corien Bary & Janneke Huitink (eds.) - 2005 - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics.