Switch to: References

Citations of:

Anaphora and Semantic Structure

In Barbara H. Partee (ed.), Compositionality in Formal Semantics - Selected Papers by Barbara H. Partee. Blackwell. pp. 122--152 (1980)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. What Mary Did Yesterday: Reflections on Knowledge-wh.Berit Brogaard - 2009 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 78 (2):439 - 467.
    Reductionists about knowledge-wh hold that "s knows-wh" (e.g. "John knows who stole his car") is reducible to "there is a proposition p such that s knows that p, and p answers the indirect question of the wh-clause." Anti-reductionists hold that "s knows-wh" is reducible to "s knows that p, as the true answer to the indirect question of the wh-clause." I argue that both of these positions are defective. I then offer a new analysis of knowledge-wh as a special kind (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Reference to Abstract Objects in Discourse.Nicholas Asher - 1993 - Dordrecht, Boston, and London: Kluwer.
    This volume is about abstract objects and the ways we refer to them in natural language. Asher develops a semantical and metaphysical analysis of these entities in two stages. The first reflects the rich ontology of abstract objects necessitated by the forms of language in which we think and speak. A second level of analysis maps the ontology of natural language metaphysics onto a sparser domain--a more systematic realm of abstract objects that are fully analyzed. This second level reflects the (...)
  • Gapping as constituent coordination.Mark J. Steedman - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (2):207 - 263.
  • Such: Binding and the pro-adjective. [REVIEW]Muffy E. A. Siegel - 1994 - Linguistics and Philosophy 17 (5):481 - 497.
    The facts aboutsuch, then, indicate not just thatsuch is a pro-adjective, but also that binding conditions apply broadly to pro-ADJs and pro-CNs, as well as to a wide range of pro-arguments. If this is true, the CN binding process accomplished by rules (40) and (41) might better be expressed in a system that uses a Cooper (1979) store mechanism. In fact, Stump (p. 144) notes that this could easily be done. Meanings of the type of∨ P n could be stored, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Connectivity in Specificational Sentences.Yael Sharvit - 1999 - Natural Language Semantics 7 (3):299-339.
    This paper is concerned with the relationship between the semantics of specificational and predicational sentences and the Connectivity effects they display. It discusses the advantages and disadvantages of semantic and syntactic approaches to Connectivity (the ‘unconstrained-be theory’, the ‘question-in-disguise theory’, and the ‘unclefting theory’), concluding that a semantic theory of Connectivity is not only preferable, but necessary. The paper also discusses the implications of such a move regarding Binding phenomena (i.e., Principle A, B, and C effects): adopting a semantic theory (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Non-redundancy: Towards a semantic reinterpretation of binding theory.Philippe Schlenker - 2005 - Natural Language Semantics 13 (1):1-92.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • On parasitic gaps.Ivan A. Sag - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (1):35 - 45.
  • Coreference and bound anaphora: A restatement of the anaphora questions. [REVIEW]Tanya Reinhart - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (1):47 - 88.
  • Formal Semantics: Origins, Issues, Early Impact.Barbara H. Partee - 2010 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6 (1).
    Formal semantics is an approach to SEMANTICS1, the study of meaning, with roots in logic, the philosophy of language, and linguistics, and since the 1980’s a core area of linguistic theory. Characteristics of formal semantics to be treated in this article include the following: Formal semanticists treat meaning as mind-independent (though abstract), contrasting with the view of meanings as concepts “in the head” (see I-LANGUAGE AND E-LANGUAGE and MEANING EXTERNALISM AND INTERNALISM); formal semanticists distinguish semantics from knowledge of semantics (Lewis (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Formal Semantics: Origins, Issues, Early Impact.Barbara H. Partee - 2011 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6:13.
    Formal semantics and pragmatics as they have developed since the late 1960's have been shaped by fruitful interdisciplinary collaboration among linguists, philosophers, and logicians, among others, and in turn have had noticeable effects on developments in syntax, philosophy of language, computational linguistics, and cognitive science.In this paper I describe the environment in which formal semantics was born and took root, highlighting the differences in ways of thinking about natural language semantics in linguistics and in philosophy and logic. With Montague as (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Preface.Ewan Klein - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (1):3-4.
  • Representing de re beliefs.Thomas J. McKay - 1991 - Linguistics and Philosophy 14 (6):711 - 739.
  • The Other Francis Bacon: On Non-BARE Proper Names.Ora Matushansky - 2015 - Erkenntnis 80 (2):335-362.
    In this paper I provide novel arguments for the predicative approach to proper names, which claims that argument proper names are definite descriptions containing a naming predicate . I first argue that modified proper names, such as the incomparable Maria Callas or the other Francis Bacon cannot be handled on the hypothesis that argument proper names have no internal structure and uniformly denote entities. I then discuss cases like every Adolf, which would normally be interpreted as every individual named Adolf (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Non-clause-bounded reflexives in modern icelandic.Joan Maling - 1984 - Linguistics and Philosophy 7 (3):211 - 241.
  • Scope and comparatives.Richard K. Larson - 1988 - Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (1):1 - 26.
  • Compositionality and the analysis of anaphora.Fred Landman & Ieke Moerdijk - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (1):89 - 114.
  • Type-driven translation.Ewan Klein & Ivan A. Sag - 1985 - Linguistics and Philosophy 8 (2):163 - 201.
  • Unbounded reflexives.Beom-Mo Kang - 1988 - Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (4):415 - 456.
  • On the treatment of complex predicates in categorial grammar.Beom-Mo Kang - 1995 - Linguistics and Philosophy 18 (1):61 - 81.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paycheck Pronouns, Bach-Peters Sentences, and Variable-Free Semantics.Pauline Jacobson - 2000 - Natural Language Semantics 8 (2):77-155.
    This paper argues for the hypothesis of direct compositionality (as in, e.g., Montague 1974), according to which the combinatory syntactic rules specify a set of well-formed expressions while the semantic combinatory rules work in tandem to directly supply a model-theoretic interpretation to each expression as it is "built" in the syntax. (This thus obviates the need for any level like LF and, concomitantly, for any rules mapping surface structures to such a level.) I focus here on one related group of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • On The Relation of Connectivity and Specificational Pseudoclefts.Daphna Heller - 2002 - Natural Language Semantics 10 (4):243-284.
    From Higgins (1973) to Iatridou and Varlokosta (1998), connectivity has been considered in the literature to be a defining characteristic of specificational pseudoclefts. This paper argues against this view based on an analysis of specificational pseudoclefts in Hebrew. Pseudoclefts in Hebrew are interesting in two ways. First, predicational and specificational pseudoclefts are distinguished lexically in the choice of the copula. Second, specificational pseudoclefts fall into two classes, each exhibiting a different set of connectivity effects. The connectivity pattern in Hebrew is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Generalized phrase structure grammar and japanese reflexivization.Takao Gunji - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (1):115 - 156.
  • On obligatory control.Donka F. Farkas - 1988 - Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (1):27 - 58.
  • Parasitic gaps.Elisabet Engdahl - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (1):5 - 34.
  • On recent analyses of the semantics of control.David R. Dowty - 1985 - Linguistics and Philosophy 8 (3):291 - 331.
  • Nominalization and Montague grammar: A semantics without types for natural languages.Gennaro Chierchia - 1982 - Linguistics and Philosophy 5 (3):303 - 354.
    We started from the fact that type theory, in the way it was implemented in IL, makes it costly to deal with nominalization processes. We have also argued that the type hierarchy as such doesn't play any real role in a grammar; the classification it provides for different semantic objects is already contained, in some sense, in the categorial structure of the grammar itself. So, on the basis of a theory of properties (Cocchiarella's HST*) we have tried to build a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Scope control and grammatical dependencies.Alastair Butler - 2007 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 16 (3):241-264.
    This paper develops a semantics with control over scope relations using Vermeulen’s stack valued assignments as information states. This makes available a limited form of scope reuse and name switching. The goal is to have a general system that fixes available scoping effects to those that are characteristic of natural language. The resulting system is called Scope Control Theory, since it provides a theory about what scope has to be like in natural language. The theory is shown to replicate a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Crossover Situations.Daniel Büring - 2004 - Natural Language Semantics 12 (1):23-62.
    Situation semantics as conceived in Kratzer (1989) has been shown to be a valuable companion to the e-type pronoun analysis of donkey sentences (Heim 1990, and recently refined in Elbourne 2001b), and more generally binding out of DP (BOOD; Tomioka 1999; Büring 2001). The present paper proposes a fully compositional version of such a theory, which is designed to capture instances of crossover in BOOD.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Remark on Jacobson 1999: Crossover as a local constraint. [REVIEW]Chris Barker - 2004 - Linguistics and Philosophy 28 (4):447 - 472.
  • Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 9.Emar Maier, Corien Bary & Janneke Huitink (eds.) - 2005 - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics.
  • Anaphora.Jeffrey C. King & Karen S. Lewis - 2016 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Disjoint reference and the typology of pronouns.Paul Kiparsky - unknown
    Obviation versus Blocking. Two approaches to the distribution of anaphors and pronominals have been explored in Binding Theory. The OBVIATION approach, originating in Lasnik 1976 and extensively developed in the GB tradition, posits autonomous disjoint reference principles which directly filter out illicit coindexations in certain structural domains. The BLOCKING approach treats disjoint reference derivatively, by making anaphors obligatory under coreference in the binding domain, and invoking a syntactic or pragmatic principle that forces disjoint reference pronominals in the “elsewhere” case.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Minimize restrictors!(Notes on definite descriptions, condition cand epithets).Philippe Schlenker - 2005 - In Emar Maier, Corien Bary & Janneke Huitink (eds.), Proceedings of Sub9.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Anaphora and the logic of change.Reinhard Muskens - 1991 - In Jan Van Eijck (ed.), Logics in AI, Proceedings of JELIA '90, volume 478 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. pp. 412-427.
    This paper shows how the dynamic interpretation of natural language introduced in work by Hans Kamp and Irene Heim can be modeled in classical type logic. This provides a synthesis between Richard Montague's theory of natural language semantics and the work by Kamp and Heim.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations