Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Джон лок про мовчання як аргумент і прояв поваги в аргументації.Олена Щербина & Наталія Щербина - 2019 - Sententiae 38 (2):6-18.
    In the article, referring to the method of rational reconstruction described by R. Rorty, an analysis of some works of J. Locke has been made in order to identify new prospects in John Locke's philosophy researches. As a result, it’s been demonstrated the presence of silence as an argument and a manifestation of respect J. Locke’s research of realms of cognition, political philosophy and philosophy of education. This is not covered in modern John Locke's philosophy researches. The authors emphasize that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Politics, Violence and Revolutionary Virtue: Reflections On Locke and Sorel.Elizabeth Frazer & Kimberly Hutchings - 2009 - Thesis Eleven 97 (1):46-63.
    John Locke (1632—1704) and Georges Sorel (1859—1922) are commonly understood as representing opposed positions vis-a-vis revolution — with Locke representing the liberal distinction between violence and politics versus Sorel's rejection of politics in its pacified liberal sense. This interpretation is shown by a close reading of their works to be misleading. Both draw a necessary link between revolution and violence, and both mediate this link through the concept of `war'. They both depoliticize revolution, as for both of them `war' is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Healing the nation's wounds: Royal ritual and experimental philosophy in restoration England.Simon Werrett - 2000 - History of Science 38 (4):377-399.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Silence as an Argument and a Manifestation of Respect in the Argumentation in John Locke's Works.Olena Shcherbyna & Nataliia Shcherbyna - 2019 - Sententiae 38 (2):6-18.
    In the article, referring to the method of rational reconstruction described by R. Rorty, an analysis of some works of J. Locke has been made in order to identify new prospects in John Locke's philosophy researches. As a result, it’s been demonstrated the presence of silence as an argument and a manifestation of respect J. Locke’s research of realms of cognition, political philosophy and philosophy of education. This is not covered in modern John Locke's philosophy researches. The authors emphasize that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Locke, liberty, and law: Legalism and extra-legal powers in the Second Treatise.Assaf Sharon - 2022 - European Journal of Political Theory 21 (2):230-252.
    The apparent inconsistency between Locke’s commitment to legalism and his explicit endorsement of the extra-legal power of prerogative has confounded many readers. Among those who don’t ignore or dismiss it, the common approach is to qualify the role or scope of prerogative. The article advocates the opposite approach. It argues that Locke’s legalism should be understood within the context of his oft neglected conception of political liberty in terms of self-government. This not only allows for the reconciliation of Locke’s legalism (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • John Locke: Optimist or pessimist?1.Peter A. Schouls - 1994 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 2 (2):51 – 73.
  • ‘Interpretation’ and the ‘Empirical’: Similarities between theoretical and empirical political science.John Gunnell Paul A. Passavant - 2015 - Contemporary Political Theory 14 (3):256.
  • ‘Interpretation’ and the ‘Empirical’: Similarities between theoretical and empirical political science.Paul A. Passavant & John Gunnell - 2015 - Contemporary Political Theory 14 (3):256-275.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ‘This man is my property’: Slavery and political absolutism in Locke and the classical social contract tradition.Johan Olsthoorn & Laurens van Apeldoorn - 2022 - European Journal of Political Theory 21 (2):253-275.
    It is morally impossible, Locke argued, for individuals to consensually establish absolute rule over themselves. That would be to transfer to rulers a power that is not ours, but God’s alone: ownership of our lives. This article analyses the conceptual presuppositions of Locke’s argument for the moral impossibility of self-enslavement through a comparison with other classical social contract theorists, including Grotius, Hobbes and Pufendorf. Despite notoriously defending the permissibility of voluntary enslavement of individuals and even entire peoples, Grotius similarly endorsed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Security, Liberty and the Myth of Balance: Towards a Critique of Security Politics.Mark Neocleous - 2007 - Contemporary Political Theory 6 (2):131.
    This article aims to challenge the idea of a 'balance' between security and liberty. Set against the background of ever greater demands for security, the article argues that the idea of balance is an essentially liberal myth, a myth that in turn masks the fact that liberalism's key category is not liberty, but security. This fact, it is suggested, undermines any possibility of liberalism challenging current demands for greater security, as witnessed by the thoroughly authoritarian 'concessions' to security by some (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Poder político fiduciario y soberanía popular. Libertad política, confianza y revolución en la filosofía política de Locke.Jordi Mundó - 2020 - Daimon: Revista Internacional de Filosofía 81:33-48.
    La teoría republicana moderna de la concepción revolucionaria de la soberanía popular tuvo un eslabón fundamental en la filosofía política de John Locke, quien elaboró un argumento en favor de la libertad natural y de la autonomía de juicio de los individuos, y en contra de la sujeción natural y la alienación de la libertad política. Concibe la autoridad política como un poder político fiduciario instituido para el fin del bien público. Cuando los gobernantes actúan para fines distintos de los (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La constitución fiduciaria de la libertad política.Jordi Mundó - 2017 - Isegoría 57:433.
    Algunas formulaciones de la filosofía política reciente han descuidado el carácter históricamente indexado de conceptos como libertad política, propiedad o soberanía, propiciando un uso anacrónico e impreciso de su significado. No obstante, su posición académica y social dominante informa el «sentido común» filosófico- político de nuestra época. Locke constituye un ejemplo de cómo la coyuntura interpretativa liberal, que se desplegó en el siglo XIX y se consolidó en el XX, ha oscurecido una parte de la complejidad y pluralidad de las (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • On political participation, rights and redistribution: a Lockean perspective.Miriam Bentwich - 2009 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 12 (4):491-511.
    Various quantitative analyses have stressed the connection between lower socioeconomic status (SES) and low political participation. The general argument behind these studies was that since political participation is crucial for democracy, and since low SES compromises political participation, liberal democratic governments cannot afford such a compromise. This paper argues that presenting political participation as a democratic value, corresponding to a ‘positive’ right, places the implied argumentation of such studies in a potential conflict with classical liberalism and its contemporary ‘successors’, emphasizing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Speaking Platitudes to Power: Observing American Business Ethics in an Age of Declining Hegemony. [REVIEW]Richard Marens - 2010 - Journal of Business Ethics 94 (S2):239 - 253.
    Over the last generation, American Business Ethics has focused excessively on the process of managerial decision-making while ignoring the collective impact of these decisions and avoiding other approaches that might earn the disapproval of corporate executives. This narrowness helped the field establish itself during the 1980s, when American management, under pressure from finance and heightened competition, was unreceptive to any limitations on its autonomy. Relying, however, on top-down approaches inspired by Aristotle, Locke, and Kant, while ignoring the consequentialism of Mill (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Machiavelli, Neville and the seventeenth-century English Republican attack on priestcraft.Gaby Mahlberg - 2018 - Intellectual History Review 28 (1):79-99.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • John Locke on Inference and Fallacy, A Re-Appraisal.Mark Garrett Longaker - 2014 - Informal Logic 34 (4):364-392.
    John Locke, long associated with the “standard” approach to fallacies and the “logical” approach to valid inference, had both logical and dialectical reasons for favoring certain proofs and denigrating others. While the logical approach to argumentation stands forth in Locke’s philosophical writings, a dialectical approach can be found in his contributions to public controversies regarding religion and toleration. Understanding Locke’s dialectical approach to argumentation not only makes his work more relevant to the contemporary discipline of informal logic, but this understanding (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On behalf of rights.David Little - 2006 - Journal of Religious Ethics 34 (2):287-310.
    ABSTRACTThough responses to Stout's book, Democracy and Tradition, have touched on his discussion of rights, none has comprehensively examined his position on the subject. Having endorsed several objections Stout raises against some influential views on democracy and rights, this article proceeds to criticize Stout's description and theoretical account of the natural and human rights traditions. The central argument is that Stout cannot successfully both affirm the traditions and adhere to his account.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Liberal conduct.Duncan Ivison - 1993 - History of the Human Sciences 6 (3):25-59.
    A philosophical genealogy of the development of liberal 'arts of government' through the work of John Locke and Michel Foucault.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cultural Politics, Political Innovation, and the Work of Human Rights.David R. Hiley - 2011 - Contemporary Pragmatism 8 (1):47-60.
    In his final collection of philosophical papers, Richard Rorty continued his attack on the traditional conception of philosophy by arguing that many of our debates should be thought of as matters of cultural politics rather than about ontology or truth. Consistent with that view, Rorty had argued that we come to see debates about human rights not as an attempt to ground rights in human nature but rather as attempts to expand our moral imagination. I extend this claim to an (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • From natural disability to the moral man: Calvinism and the history of psychology.C. F. Goodey - 2001 - History of the Human Sciences 14 (3):1-29.
    Some humanist theologians within the French Reformed Church in the 17th century developed the notion that a disability of the intellect could exist in nature independently of any moral defect, freeing its possessors from any obligations of natural law. Sharpened by disputes with the church leadership, this notion began to suggest a species-type classification that threatened to override the importance of the boundary between elect and reprobate in the doctrine of predestination. This classification seems to look forward to the natural (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Digger Radicalism and Agrarian Capitalism.Geoff Kennedy - 2006 - Historical Materialism 14 (3):113-143.
  • Owning land versus governing a land: Property, sovereignty, and nationalism: Sam Fleischacker.Sam Fleischacker - 2013 - Social Philosophy and Policy 30 (1-2):373-403.
    This essay attempts to clarify the distinction between property and sovereignty, and to bring out the importance of that distinction to a liberal nationalism. Beginning with common intuitions about what distinguishes our rights to our possessions from the state's rightful governance over us, it proceeds to explore some historical sources of these intuitions, and the importance of a sharp distinction between ownership and governance to the rise of liberalism. From here, the essay moves into an exploration of group ownership, and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Security, Liberty and the Myth of Balance: Towards a Critique of Security Politics.Robyn Eckersley - 2007 - Contemporary Political Theory 6 (2):131-149.
    This article aims to challenge the idea of a ‘balance’ between security and liberty. Set against the background of ever greater demands for security, the article argues that the idea of balance is an essentially liberal myth, a myth that in turn masks the fact that liberalism's key category is not liberty, but security. This fact, it is suggested, undermines any possibility of liberalism challenging current demands for greater security, as witnessed by the thoroughly authoritarian ‘concessions’ to security by some (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Elementos da liberdade republicana em John Locke.Rodrigo Ribeiro de Sousa - 2018 - Cadernos Espinosanos 38:171-188.
    Ao longo da história da filosofia, John Locke tem sido frequentemente associado à tradição do liberalismo político, o que decorre, invariavelmente, de um modo peculiar de interpretação da noção de liberdade para o filósofo, que estaria estruturada em torno da ideia de não-interferência. Derivada frequentemente de propostas analíticas realizadas em um “vácuo histórico”, em que as ideias de Locke são tomadas como uma estática coleção, tal conclusão expressa uma perspectiva que não considera o caráter essencialmente discursivo da filosofia política e (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constructing ‘Englishness’ and promoting ‘politeness’ through a ‘Francophobic’ bestseller: Télémaque in England (1699–1745). [REVIEW]Aris Della Fontana - 2020 - History of European Ideas 46 (6):766-792.
    ABSTRACT This article draws attention to the reception that François Fénelon's Télémaque (1699) received in England in the first half of the eighteenth century. It overturns the historiographical assumption that the Jacobites were the leading disseminators of this continental bestseller on the other side of the Channel. Even though in the English intellectual context Télémaque's framework was unorthodox, many staunch supporters of the Glorious Revolution were fascinated by the book's portrayal of a virtuous king who respects laws, rights and liberties, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hobbes’s and Locke’s Contract Theories: Political not Metaphysical.Deborah Baumgold - 2005 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 8 (3):289-308.
    Abstract Inspired by Rawls?s admission that his twentieth?century contract theory builds in the parochial horizon of modern constitutional democracy, this essay critically examines two truisms about seventeenth?century contract theory. The first is the stock view that the English case is irrelevant to the logic of Leviathan and the Second Treatise. To the contrary, I argue that their political conclusions depend on introducing constitutional and legal ?facts?, in particular, facts about the constitution of the English monarchy. Second, I challenge the Whiggish (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Behalf of Rights: A Critique of "Democracy and Tradition". [REVIEW]David Little - 2006 - Journal of Religious Ethics 34 (2):287 - 310.
    Though responses to Stout's book, "Democracy and Tradition," have touched on his discussion of rights, none has comprehensively examined his position on the subject. Having endorsed several objections Stout raises against some influential views on democracy and rights, this article proceeds to criticize Stout's description and theoretical account of the natural and human rights traditions. The central argument is that Stout cannot successfully both affirm the traditions and adhere to his account.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The language of liberty, 1660–1832: Political discourse and social dynamics in the Anglo-American World.Richard Connors - 1996 - History of European Ideas 22 (2):137-140.
    (1996). The language of liberty, 1660–1832: Political discourse and social dynamics in the Anglo-American World. History of European Ideas: Vol. 22, No. 2, pp. 137-140.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Lockeian liberalism” and “classical republicanism”: the formation, function and failure of the categories.J. C. D. Clark - 2023 - Intellectual History Review 33 (1):11-31.
    The contest between “Lockeian liberalism” and “classical republicanism” as explanatory frameworks for the intellectual history of the American Revolution, and therefore of the present-day United States, has been one of the longest running and most distinguished in recent U.S. historiography. It also has major implications for the history of political thought in the North Atlantic Anglophone world more widely. Yet this debate was merely suspended when it was held to have ended in an ill-defined compromise. Although some U.S. historians expressed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Requisitos patrimoniales y participación política en la obra de John Locke.Joan Severo Chumbita - 2018 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 55:337-336.
    La relación entre patrimonio y derechos políticos en la obra de John Locke ha sido ampliamente discutida. Por un lado, se encuentran posiciones como las de Kendall y Tully que atribuyen un carácter democrático a la concepción lockeana sobre la sociedad civil. Por otro, interpretaciones como las de Ashcraft que le asignan un sesgo revolucionario e igualitario, próximo a la concepción de los Levellers. Sin embargo, a la luz de una serie de documentos, es posible discutir estas interpretaciones, como ya (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The empire of political thought: civilization, savagery and perceptions of Indigenous government.Bruce Buchan - 2005 - History of the Human Sciences 18 (2):1-22.
    This paper examines the relationship between understandings of Indigenous government and the development of early-modern European, and especially British, political thought. It will be argued that a range of British political thinkers represented Indigenous peoples as being in want of effective government and regular conduct due to the absence of sufficiently developed property relations among them. In particular, British political thinkers framed the ‘deficiencies’ of Indigenous people by ideas of civilization in which key assumptions connected ‘property’, ‘government’, and ‘society’ as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mary Astell: Defender of the "Disembodied Mind".Cynthia B. Bryson - 1998 - Hypatia 13 (4):40 - 62.
    This paper demonstrates how Mary Astell's version of Cartesian dualism supports her disavowal of female subordination and traditional gender roles, her rejection of Locke's notion of "thinking matter" as a major premise for rejecting his political philosophy of "social contracts" between men and women, and, finally, her claim that there is no intrinsic difference between genders in terms of ratiocination, the primary assertion that grants her the title of the first female English feminist.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mary Astell: Defender of the “Disembodied Mind”.Cynthia B. Bryson - 1998 - Hypatia 13 (4):40-62.
    This paper demonstrates how Mary Astell's version of Cartesian dualism supports her disavowal of female subordination and traditional gender roles, her rejection of Locke's notion of “thinking matter” as a major premise for rejecting his political philosophy of “social contracts” between men and women, and, finally, her claim that there is no intrinsic difference between genders in terms of ratiocination, the primary assertion that grants her the title of the first female English feminist.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Parsing Macpherson: The Last Rites of Locke the Possessive Individualist.Hugh Breakey - 2013 - Theoria 80 (1):62-83.
    C.B. Macpherson's “Possessive Individualist” reading of Locke is one of the most radical and influential interpretations in the history of exegesis. Despite a substantial critical response over the past five decades, Macpherson's reading remains orthodox in various circles in the humanities generally, particularly in legal studies, and his interpretation of several crucial passages has unwittingly been followed even by his sharpest critics within Lockean scholarship. In order to present the definitive rebuttal to this interpretation, and so finally to lay it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Liberalism and the problem of poverty.Richard Ashcraft - 1992 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 6 (4):493-516.
    From the seventeenth to the mid?nineteenth centuries, the language of natural law and natural rights structured the commitment of liberalism to the development of both a market society and democratic political institutions. The existence of widespread poverty was seen, at various times, as a problem to be resolved either by an expanding commercial/capitalistic society or through democratic political reform. As Thomas Home shows in Property Rights and Poverty, liberalism as apolitical theory has, from its origins, been deeply committed to (at (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Tradition and Prudence in Locke's Exceptions to Toleration.David J. Lorenzo - 2003 - American Journal of Political Science 47 (2):248-58.
    Why did Locke exclude Catholics and atheists from toleration? Not, I contend, because he was trapped by his context, but because his prudential approach and practica ljudgments led him to traditiona ltexts. I make this argumentfirst by outlining the connections among prudential exceptionality, practical judgments, and traditional texts. I then describe important continuities betweenc onventional English understandings of the relationship between state and religion and Locke's writings on toleration, discuss Locke's conception of rights, and illustrate his use of prudential exceptions (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hobbes’ Anti-liberal Individualism.James Martel - 2016 - Las Torres de Lucca: Revista Internacional de Filosofía Política 5 (9):31-59.
    In much of the literature on Hobbes, he is considered a proto-liberal, that is, he is seen as setting up the apparatus that leads to liberalism but his own authoritarian streak makes it impossible for liberals to completely claim him as one of their own. In this paper, I argue that, far from being a precursor to liberalism, Hobbes offers a political theory that is implicitly anti-liberal. I do not mean this in the conventional sense that Hobbes was too conservative (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Lasst uns den Weg einer neuen Ontologie einschlagen! (Teil 1).Gianluigi Segalerba - 2017 - Analele Universitatii Din Craiova, Seria Filosofie 40 (2):91-183.
    The present essay is the first part of an analysis regarding aspects of Aristotle’s ontology. Aristotle’s ontology is, in my opinion, a formal ontology that examines the fundamental structures of reality and that investigates the features belonging to entities such as substance, quantity, quality, universals. Aristotle’s ontology investigates, moreover, the reciprocal relations existing between these entities. Aristotle’s interpretation of universals is not, in my opinion, a nominalist interpretation of universals: I do not think Aristotle regards universals as being only mental (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lockean theories of property: Justifications for unilateral appropriation.Karl Widerquist - 2010 - Public Reason 2 (1):3-26.
    Although John Locke’s theory of appropriation is undoubtedly influential, no one seems to agree about exactly what he was trying to say. It is unlikely that someone will write the interpretation that effectively ends the controversy. Instead of trying to find the one definitive interpretation of Locke’s property theory, this article attempts to identify the range of reasonable interpretations and extensions of Lockean property theory that exist in the contemporary literature with an emphasis on his argument for unilateral appropriation. It (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations