Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Nāgārjuna’s Scepticism about Philosophy.Ethan A. Mills - 2020 - In Oren Hanner (ed.), Buddhism and Scepticism: Historical, Philosophical, and Comparative Perspectives. Freiburg/Bochum: ProjektVerlag. pp. 55-81.
  • Nāgārjuna’s Arguments on Motion Revisited.Jan Westerhoff - 2008 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 36 (4):455-479.
    This paper discusses a somewhat neglected reading of the second chapter of Nāgārjuna’s Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, arguing that the main focus of a crucial part is a particular theory of properties and their relation to individuals they instantiate, rather than the refutation of specific assumptions about the nature of space and time. Some of Nāgārjuna’s key arguments about motion should be understood as argument templates in which notions other than mover, motion, and so forth could be substituted. The remainder of the discussion (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the formal arguments of the akutobhayā.Joseph Walser - 1998 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 26 (3):189-232.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The earliest indian reference to muslims in a buddhist philosophical text of circa 700.Leonard W. J. Van Der Kuijp - 2006 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 34 (3):169-202.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dependent Arising, Non-arising, and the Mind: MMK1 and the Abhidharma.Mattia Salvini - 2014 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 42 (4):471-497.
    The first Chapter of Nāgārjuna’s Mūlamadhyamakakārikā offers a critique of causation that includes the Abhidharmic category of the ‘four conditions’. Following the South-Asian commentarial tradition, this article discusses the precise relationship between Madhyamaka philosophy and its fundamental Abhidharmic background. What comes to light is a more precise assessment of Madhyamaka ideas about viable conventions, understood as the process of dependent arising. Since this is primarily in the sense of conceptual dependence, it involves sentiency as a necessary causal element, and the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Nāgārjuna’s Negation.Chris Rahlwes - 2022 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 50 (2):307-344.
    The logical analysis of Nāgārjuna’s catuṣkoṭi has remained a heated topic for logicians in Western academia for nearly a century. At the heart of the catuṣkoṭi, the four corners’ formalization typically appears as: A, Not A, Both, and Neither. The pulse of the controversy is the repetition of negations in the catuṣkoṭi. Westerhoff argues that Nāgārjuna in the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā uses two different negations: paryudāsa and prasajya-pratiṣedha. This paper builds off Westerhoff’s account and presents some subtleties of Nāgārjuna’s use of these (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The examination of conditioned entities and the examination of reality.Paul Nietupski - 1996 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 24 (2):103-143.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • From brahmanism to buddhism.Christian Lindtner - 1999 - Asian Philosophy 9 (1):5 – 37.
    It is argued that early Buddhism to a very considerable extent can and should be seen as reformed Brahmanism. Speculations about cosmogony in Buddhist s tras can be traced back to Vedic sources, above all R gveda 10.129 & 10.90—two hymns that play a similar fundamental role in the early Upanisads. Like the immortal and unmanifest Brahman and the mortal and manifest Brahm, the Buddha, as a mythological Bhagavat, also had two forms. In his highest form he is “the profound” (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Dimensions of Candrakīrti’s Conventional Reality.Shenghai Li - 2019 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 47 (1):49-72.
    Although Candrakīrti has been a focus in the recent scholarly attention on conventional reality in Buddhist philosophy, the complexity of his discussions of the status of phenomenal world on the surface or conventional level has not been adequately explored. In cataloging the wide-ranging interpretations that Candrakīrti has offered, this paper identifies several clusters of connected ideas that are delineated here as dimensions of Candrakīrti’s conventional reality. It will be shown that his thoughts on the subject have divergent orientations, ranging from (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From Etymology to Ontology: Vasubandhu and Candrakīrti on Various Interpretations of Pratītyasamutpāda.Goran Kardas - 2015 - Asian Philosophy 25 (3):293-317.
    The main body of this article presents Vasubandhu’s and Candrakīrti’s discussion on the etymology of pratītyasamutpāda and its meaning as it appears in the Bhāṣya to Abhidharmakośa 3.28ab and Prasannapadā 4.5–9.27, respectively. Both authors put forward and critically examine various Buddhist grammatical analyses and interpretations of the term. Many passages in the indicated sections parallel or nearly parallel to each other suggest that Buddhist discussions on pratītyasamutpāda were held in a very specified manner during the mature phase of Buddhist philosophy (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bh?vaviveka's Praj�?prad?pa.William L. Ames - 1994 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 (2):93-135.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations