Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Judith Shklar on the problem of political motivation.Eleanor Pickford - forthcoming - History of European Ideas.
    The political thought of Judith Shklar is often invoked by contemporary theorists of realism in support of their arguments. This article contends, however, that realist discussion of Shklar has overlooked a concern central to her thought – the worry that individuals are often unwilling to reevaluate their views on the questions of political life. Shklar’s theoretical concern with this ‘problem of political motivation’ will be demonstrated by examining the evolution of her views on the relationship between utopia and hope, showing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ‘Painted scenes’ or ‘empty pageants’? Superficiality and depth in (realist) political thought.Demetris Tillyris & Derek Edyvane - 2022 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 48 (9):1277-1301.
    The realist injunction to attend to the ‘realities of politics’ when we do political philosophy, though obviously appropriate, is highly platitudinous. By drawing on the underappreciated realist insights of Isaiah Berlin, Stuart Hampshire and Hannah Arendt, we elaborate a neglected distinction between two antagonistic conceptions of political reality – the realism of surface and the realism of depth – and consider its implications for the recent realist turn. We illustrate how that distinction reveals some neglected tensions and incoherencies within contemporary (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ‘Painted scenes’ or ‘empty pageants’? Superficiality and depth in (realist) political thought.Demetris Tillyris & Derek Edyvane - 2022 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 48 (9):1277-1301.
    Philosophy & Social Criticism, Volume 48, Issue 9, Page 1277-1301, November 2022. The realist injunction to attend to the ‘realities of politics’ when we do political philosophy, though obviously appropriate, is highly platitudinous. By drawing on the underappreciated realist insights of Isaiah Berlin, Stuart Hampshire and Hannah Arendt, we elaborate a neglected distinction between two antagonistic conceptions of political reality – the realism of surface and the realism of depth – and consider its implications for the recent realist turn. We (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ‘Painted scenes’ or ‘empty pageants’? Superficiality and depth in (realist) political thought.Demetris Tillyris & Derek Edyvane - 2022 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 48 (9):1277-1301.
    The realist injunction to attend to the ‘realities of politics’ when we do political philosophy, though obviously appropriate, is highly platitudinous. By drawing on the underappreciated realist insights of Isaiah Berlin, Stuart Hampshire and Hannah Arendt, we elaborate a neglected distinction between two antagonistic conceptions of political reality – the realism of surface and the realism of depth – and consider its implications for the recent realist turn. We illustrate how that distinction reveals some neglected tensions and incoherencies within contemporary (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The knowledge of suffering: On Judith Shklar’s ‘Putting Cruelty First’.Kamila Stullerova - 2014 - Contemporary Political Theory 13 (1):23-45.
    Stullerova, K.. The Knowledge of Suffering: On Judith Shklar's 'Putting Cruelty First'. Contemporary Political Theory, 13, 23-45.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The knowledge of suffering: On Judith Shklar|[rsquo]|s |[lsquo]|Putting Cruelty First|[rsquo]|.Kamila Stullerova - 2014 - Contemporary Political Theory 13 (1):23.
    Judith Shklar’s dictum, ‘the worst evil of cruelty’, is well known. What this means for her political theory and how such theory is construed are rarely explored. This article maintains that Shklar’s turn towards cruelty/suffering has a specific role in the development of her political argument. It allows her both to curb her long-standing skepticism, and to use it creatively. This is because suffering must be examined from the perspectives of history and philosophy, which produce two sets of knowledge, each (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • El liberalismo de Friedrich A. Hayek y Judith N. Shklar: una comparación.Paloma De la Nuez Sánchez-Cascado - 2019 - Araucaria 21 (41).
    La comparación entre el pensamiento político de dos grandes liberales, Judith N. Shklar y Friedrich A. Hayek, además de constituir una empresa intelectual sumamente estimulante, resulta muy útil para comprender la evolución del pensamiento político liberal en el siglo XX. Shklar, cuyo reconocimiento internacional está creciendo sin cesar en los últimos años, escribe que el liberalismo se hace contra el totalitarismo como doctrina política que pone por encima de cualquier otro valor la libertad, principio también fundamental en la obra de (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Historical memory, democratic citizenship, and political theory: Reconstructing a historical method in Judith Shklar’s writings.Simon Sihang Luo - 2023 - European Journal of Political Theory 22 (2):324-345.
    Judith Shklar has been invoked by contemporary realists as an example of how history is a better source of political knowledge than abstract philosophy. This emphasis on history challenges the predominant understanding of her political theory that stresses the universality of fear of cruelty. This contrast between history and moral universalism invites a serious investigation of Shklar's historical method. This article takes up this task by reconstructing a Shklarian historical method based on a tripartite relation between historical memory, democratic citizenship, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hope and memory in the thought of Judith Shklar.Katrina Forrester - 2011 - Modern Intellectual History 8 (3):591-620.
    Current interpretations of the political theory of Judith Shklar focus to a disabling extent on her short, late article (1989); commentators take this late essay as representative of her work as a whole and thus characterize her as an anti-totalitarian, Cold War liberal. Other interpretations situate her political thought alongside followers of John Rawls and liberal political philosophy. Challenging the centrality of fear in Shklar's thought, this essay examines her writings on utopian and normative thought, the role of history in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Cruelty, Injustice, and the Liberalism of Fear.Robin Douglass - 2023 - Political Theory 51 (5):790-813.
    This article analyzes the relationship between the ideas of cruelty and injustice in Judith Shklar’s political theory. Shklar’s The Faces of Injustice is sometimes read as an instantiation of the liberalism of fear, which regards cruelty and the fear that it inspires as the summum malum. I challenge this interpretation and instead argue that her account of injustice should be read independently of her commitment to the liberalism of fear. In doing so, I show how her exploration of the faces (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Legitimacy, resistance and the stakes of politics.Adam Burgos - forthcoming - Philosophy and Social Criticism.
    This essay argues for the conceptual connection of legitimacy, resistance and ‘the people’ within liberal theories of public justification by making two primary claims: that legitimacy and resistance are mutually constitutive of one another and that together legitimacy and resistance are constitutive of an aspirational conception of ‘the people’. These claims revolve around the idea that the legitimacy of democratic regimes necessarily entails the questioning of that legitimacy through resistance, which concerns demands that say something about the makeup of ‘the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Justice as Non-maleficence.Vittorio Bufacchi - 2020 - Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory 67 (162):1-27.
    The principle of non-maleficence, primum non nocere, has deep roots in the history of moral philosophy, being endorsed by John Stuart Mill, W. D. Ross, H. L. A. Hart, Karl Popper and Bernard Gert. And yet, this principle is virtually absent from current debates on social justice. This article suggests that non-maleficence is more than a moral principle; it is also a principle of social justice. Part I looks at the origins of non-maleficence as a principle of ethics, and medical (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Consumer Rights to Informed Choice on the Food Market.Volkert Beekman - 2008 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 11 (1):61-72.
    The discourse about traceability in food chains focused on traceability as means towards the end of managing health risks. This discourse witnessed a call to broaden traceability to accommodate consumer concerns about foods that are not related to health. This call envisions the development of ethical traceability. This paper presents a justification of ethical traceability. The argument is couched in liberal distinctions, since the call for ethical traceability is based on intuitions about consumer rights to informed choice. The paper suggests (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations