Switch to: References

Citations of:

Science in flux

Boston: D. Reidel Pub. Co. (1975)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Obituary.[author unknown] - 2000 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14 (1):77-81.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Current Philosophy of Science.Joseph Agassi - 2011 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 41 (2):278-294.
    This Companion to the philosophy of science reflects fairly well the gloomy state of affairs in this subfield at its best—concerns, problems, prejudices, and all. The field is still stuck with the problem of justification of science, refusing to admit that there is neither need nor possibility to justify science and forbid dissent from it.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophical anthropology can help social scientists learn from empirical tests.John Wettersten - 2007 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 37 (3):295–318.
    Popper's theory of demarcation has set the standard of falsifiability for all sciences. But not all falsifiable theories are part of science and some tests of scientific theories are better than others. Popper's theory has led to the banning of metaphysical and/or philosophical anthropological theories from science. But Joseph Agassi has supplemented Popper's theory to explain how such theories are useful as research programs within science. This theory can also be used to explain how interesting tests may be found. Theories (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The current state of the metaphysics of science debate.Cristian Soto - 2015 - Philosophica 90 (1).
    I examine the current state of the debate on the metaphysics of science. In 1, I identify some of the main questions belonging to the MS, looking into the relationship between science and metaphysics. In 2, I expound the rise of the old wave in the MS, which endorses the belief that metaphysics is a guide to, or a heuristic for, science and outlines the stronger idea that metaphysics makes science possible. In 3, I examine the maximalist MS. This is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Metaphysics, laws, and natural kinds: Minimalist approaches: Stephen Mumford and Matthew Tugby : Metaphysics and science. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, vii+244pp, £40 HB.Cristian Soto - 2014 - Metascience 24 (2):321-331.
    Debates on the metaphysics of science have steadily gained momentum over the last decade or so. This appears to illustrate a case of philosophers’ realisation that metaphysics—and theoretical philosophy overall—largely depends upon the sciences and has a good deal to learn from them. Recent literature on this, in fact, has reached an unforeseen high level of refinement in the arguments and a very much desirable precision in the consequences that we can derive from examining the interplay currently undergoing between science (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An apt celebration of Agassi’s Career: Nimrod Bar-Am and Stefano Gattei : Encouraging openness: essays for Joseph Agassi on the occasion of his 90th birthday. Switzerland: Springer, xiv+584pp, €127 HB. [REVIEW]Cristian Soto - 2019 - Metascience 28 (3):483-486.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The politics of situating knowledge: An exercise in social epistemology. [REVIEW]Raphael Sassower - 1994 - Argumentation 8 (2):185-198.
    This essay forges links between Popperians and feminists by considering the connections between Donna Haraway's “situated knowledge” and Karl R. Popper's “situational logic.” It is concerned with the political commitments behind methodological issues, with the degree to which there can be a Popperian contribution to the feminist vision of a successor science, and with ways of dealing with, while not resolving, the political differences between socialist feminists and libertarian Popperians.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Should Anyone Care about Scientific Progress?Raphael Sassower - 2020 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 51 (1):58-90.
    Scientific progress has been understood as synonymous with the growth of knowledge and the advancement of humanity. In this brief survey, this concept is problematized both in rhetorical terms and within the neoliberal framework. Despite the sustained marketing of the scientific community and its funding agencies, the dangers associated with progress are explained and highlighted.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paranoia and reinforced dogmatism: Beyond critical rationality.Abraham Rudnick - 2003 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 33 (3):339-350.
    Deviant forms of human thought may provide insight into epistemic standards, such as rationality. A comparative analysis of paranoia and reinforced dogmatism suggests that reinforced dogmatism, such as pseudo-science a-la-Popper, demonstrates a primary epistemic lack of critical rationality, that is, of testability, whereas paranoia demonstrates a lack of range of alternative statements leading secondarily to a lack of testability. This reflects the importance to both epistemology and psychiatry of epistemic standards in addition to testability, such as relevance to problems, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Philosophical Analysis of the General Methodology of Qualitative Research: A Critical Rationalist Perspective. [REVIEW]Abraham Rudnick - 2014 - Health Care Analysis 22 (3):1-10.
    Philosophical discussion of the general methodology of qualitative research, such as that used in some health research, has been inductivist or relativist to date, ignoring critical rationalism as a philosophical approach with which to discuss the general methodology of qualitative research. This paper presents a discussion of the general methodology of qualitative research from a critical rationalist perspective (inspired by Popper), using as an example mental health research. The widespread endorsement of induction in qualitative research is positivist and is suspect, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Philosophers against “truth”: The cases of Harreacute and Laudan.A. Paya - 1995 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9 (3):255-284.
    The criticisms levelled at the notion of truth by an anti-realist and an entity-realist are critically examined. The upshot of the discussion will be that whilst neither of the two anti-truth philosophers have succeeded in establishing their cases against truth, for entity-realists to reject the notion of truth is to throw out the baby with the bath water: entity-realism without the notion of correspondence truth will degenerate into anti-realism.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Critical Assessment of the Programmes of Producing ‘Islamic Science’ and ‘Islamisation of Science/Knowledge’.Ali Paya - 2015 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29 (3):311-335.
    In the present article, working from within the framework of critical rationalism and focusing mostly on the views developed by some Iranian writers, I argue that the programmes of producing ‘Islamic Science’ and ‘Islamisation of Science/Knowledge’ are doomed to failure. I develop my arguments in three parts. I start by explaining that the advocates of the programmes of producing cIS or IoK subscribe to mistaken images of science that are shaped by either a positivist or outmoded culturalist/interpretivist theories of science. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The epistemology of J. M. Keynes.Rod O'donnell - 1990 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 41 (3):333-350.
    This paper has two objectives, neither previously attempted in the published literature—first, to outline J. M. Keynes's theory of knowledge in some detail, and, secondly, to justify the contention that his epistemology is a variety of rationalism, and not, as many have asserted, a form of empiricism. Keynes's attitude to empirical data is also analysed as well as his views on prediction and theory choice. 1This paper is partly based on ideas initially advanced in O'Donnell [1982], a revised and expanded (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • State, technology, and planning.Ingemar Nordin - 1991 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 21 (4):458-475.
    A central theme within political theory is the rational management of society based on science and technology. This idea involves several problems concerning the philosophy of technology and social engineering. Some of these difficulties, which are discussed in this essay, are (1) the scientific identification of objective needs and what we can do with it with respect to rational choice, (2) expert-management versus user-management in technical matters, (3) the nature of technology and its consequences for planning, and (4) the nature (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book Reviews : Adolf Grunbaum, Validation in the Clinical Theory of Psychoanalysis: A Study in the Philosophy of Psychoanalysis. International University Press, Madison, WI, Comm., 1993. Pp. xxii, 414. $50.00. [REVIEW]Nathaniel Laor - 1996 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 26 (3):432-435.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theoretical Pluralism and Incommensurability.Noretta Koertge - 1983 - Philosophica 31.
  • Openness to the unknown: The role of falsifiability in search of better knowledge.Yasuyuki Kageyama - 2003 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 33 (1):100-121.
    From the time of its birth, Popper’s theory of falsifiability has been fiercely criticized from various viewpoints. In the author’s view, however, those various criticisms all have the same root in their assumption that a falsification must be certain and conclusive. As the theory of falsifiability has never had such an assumption, it is the source of misunderstanding. By discarding it, we can reply to every criticism and thereby clarify the role of falsifiability in our search for better knowledge; that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Can the monster errour be slain?Giora Hon - 1991 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 5 (3):257 – 268.
    Abstract One cannot discount experimental errors and turn the attention to the logicomathematical structure of a physical theory without distorting the nature of the scientific method. The occurrence of errors in experiments constitutes an inherent feature of the attempt to test theories in the physical world. This feature deserves proper attention which has been neglected. An attempt is made to address this problem.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ad hoc auxiliary hypotheses and falsificationism.Adolf Grünbaum - 1976 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 27 (4):329-362.
  • Popper and the 7th Approximation: The Problem of Taxonomy.Bennison Gray - 1980 - Dialectica 34 (2):129-154.
    SummaryThe conspicuous role of taxonomy and debates about taxonomy in the well‐established physical science of pedology throws into question the Popperian rejection of definition and classification.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Darwin as an epistemologist.Ronald Curtis - 1987 - Annals of Science 44 (4):379-408.
    SummaryIn this article I argue that Darwin was the author, quite contrary to his original intentions, of a fundamental revolution in the theory of scientific knowledge. In 1838, in order to meet the anti-evolutionist challenge of his professional colleague, William Whewell, he began to sketch a transmutationist theory of the origin of human ideas which would explain the success of inductive science: its discovery of what Whewell and his contemporaries thought were necessary and certain truths. But though it explained how (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Linearity and Reflexivity in the Growth of Mathematical Knowledge.Leo Corry - 1989 - Science in Context 3 (2):409-440.
    The ArgumentRecent studies in the philosophy of mathematics have increasingly stressed the social and historical dimensions of mathematical practice. Although this new emphasis has fathered interesting new perspectives, it has also blurred the distinction between mathematics and other scientific fields. This distinction can be clarified by examining the special interaction of thebodyandimagesof mathematics.Mathematics has an objective, ever-expanding hard core, the growth of which is conditioned by socially and historically determined images of mathematics. Mathematics also has reflexive capacities unlike those of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Testability in the social sciences.William Berkson - 1989 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 19 (2):157-171.
  • Agassi on Technology.William Berkson - 2022 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 52 (6):365-371.
    Joseph Agassi's distinction and characterization of science, applied science, and technology—with invention connecting applied science and technology—has been a signal contribution. His theory of science, though, is flawed by his rejection of any role for corroboration, when corroboration in fact has guided researchers in various ways. His later, more extensive discussions of these issues, unfortunately have not advanced on his important early work.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Metaphysical Perspectives and Their Role in Science.Nimrod Bar-Am - 2022 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 52 (6):354-364.
    In this paper I offer a brief summary of Popper’s views on metaphysics. I then explain Agassi’s criticism of those views, and why I regard them as fruitful improvements.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fuller's civic republicanism and the question of scientific expertise.Brian S. Baigrie - 1995 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 25 (4):502-511.
  • Turner on Merton.Joseph Agassi - 2009 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 39 (2):284-293.
    Stephen Turner complains about weaknesses of Robert K. Merton's teachings without noticing that these are common. He puts down Merton's ideas despite his innovations, on the ground that they are not successful and not sufficiently revolutionary. The criteria by which he condemns Merton are too vague and too high. Merton's merit is in his having put the sociology of science on the map and drawn attention to the egalitarianism that was prominent in classical science and that is now diminished. Key (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The advantage of theft over honest toil.Joseph Agassi - 2009 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 39 (3):507-526.
    Gregory Landini offers a new and an illuminating reading of Ludwig Wittgenstein’s idea about his own innovation: it is the invention of a notation that removes the mystery from all theorems of logic and of mathematics as it renders their proofs part of their wordings. This makes all theorems in principle as boring as “all four-legged animals are animals.” This idea is Wittgenstein’s doctrine of showing. It is worthless; yet, as Landini shows, every time Wittgenstein offered an elaboration on it, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge personal or social.Joseph Agassi - 1998 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 28 (4):522-551.
    Karl Popper's methodology can be seen as the situational logic of research. Popper called his method "Epistemology without a Knowing Subject." It was dismissed as metaphysical by those who refuse to give up an ideal knowing subject (a perfect human inductive processor). This article surveys the failure of modem discussions of this ideal, from the earliest (the writings of Sir Francis Bacon) to the latest (Kripke). The knowing subject exits at last, but leaves behind interesting results. The ideal knowing subject (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Blame not the laws of nature.Joseph Agassi - 1995 - Foundations of Science 1 (1):131-154.
    1. Lies, Error and Confusion 2. Lies 3. The Demarcation of Science: Historical 4. The Demarcation of Science: Recent 5. Observed Regularities and Laws of Nature.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Touch of Malice.Joseph Agassi - 2002 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 32 (1):107-119.
  • Farewell to certitude: Einstein's novelty on induction and deduction, fallibilism.Avshalom M. Adam - 2000 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 31 (1):19-37.
    In the late 19th century great changes in theories of light and electricity were in direct conflict with certitude, the view that scientific knowledge is infallible. What is, then, the epistemic status of scientific theory? To resolve this issue Duhem and Poincaré proposed images of fallible knowledge, Instrumentalism and Conventionalism, respectively. Only in 1919–1922, after Einstein's relativity was published, he offered arguments to support Fallibilism, the view that certainty cannot be achieved in science. Though Einstein did not consider Duhem's Instrumentalism, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Rationality in inquiry : on the revisability of cognitive standards.Jonas Nilsson - 2000 - Umeå Studies in Philosophy 1:154.
    The topic of this study is to what extent standards of rational inquiry can be rationally criticized and revised. It is argued that it is rational to treat all such standards as open to criticism and revision. Arguments to the effect that we are fallible with regard to all standards of rational inquiry are presented. Standards cannot be ultimately justified and with certainty established either as adequate or as inescapable presuppositions. Apel's attempt to give ultimate justifications of certain moral and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations