Summary |
Like deductive logic, inductive logic is widely studied by logicians.
But referring to a logic of evidential support, inductive logic is basic to our
ability to get along in the world, and is a backbone of scientific reasoning.
Cause-effect inferences, generalizations and applied generalizations, and
analogical inferences are recognized as distinct but overlapping kinds of inductive
inferences. Each is ubiquitous in human thought, such that inductive,
evidence-driven reasoning appears basic to the pursuit of search for knowledge
and understanding. As defeasible or non-monotonic reasoning, inductive
arguments and inferences cannot satisfy deductive soundness: The relation of one’s
conclusion to one’s premises is enlarging or ampliative (Latin ampliare), such that there is
no contradiction in the premises of an inductive argument being true, yet the
conclusion false. The backside of this enlargement is the recognition of important
concerns about the underdetermination of theories by the facts which they
purport to explain (the underdetermination
problem) and its implications for theories of scientific explanation, and for
the aims and goals of scientific practices more generally. Whether the reasoner
is rationally entitled to appeal to a principle
of induction -- the uniformity of nature assumption that the
future will resemble the past -- or
whether our reliance upon it is more a matter of animal faith, has relatedly been
given much critical attention. At least since David Hume framed what has come
to be known as the problem of induction,
inductive skeptics and even philosophers intending to respond to Humean
skepticism have taken especial note of the inherent limitations, and many special
paradoxes and riddles, which attend our deep dependence upon inductive
reasoning. Hume’s problem has many offshoots, and questions either directly about,
or referring us back to inductive processes, continue to receive attention among
philosophers in ways that extend far beyond logic and science. There are induction-connected
problems for epistemologists, the lottery paradox as but one example, and for metaphysicians,
as when we reflect upon what justification we have even for belief in other
minds. But the very nature of inductive logic as non-monotonic logic, and inductive
reasoning as enlarging or ampliative, may be what turns inductive reasoners
from sole attention to armchair worries to empirical or evidence-driven research,
and to the pursuit of new knowledge and increasing understanding of the natural
world and our place within it. |