Results for 'Risto Hilpinen'

(not author) ( search as author name )
232 found
Order:
  1. Conditionals and possible worlds : On C.s. Peirce's conception of conditionals and modalities.Risto Hilpinen - 2011 - In Leila Haaparanta (ed.), The development of modern logic. New York: Oxford University Press.
  2.  8
    Deontische Logik und Semantik.Risto Hilpinen - 1977
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3. Realism and Anti-Realism in the Philosophy of Science Beijing International Conference, 1992.R. S. Cohen, Risto Hilpinen, Jen-Tsung Ch Iu & Beijing International Conference on Philosophy of Science - 1996
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. X*—Authors and Artifacts.Risto Hilpinen - 1993 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 93 (1):155-178.
    Risto Hilpinen; X*—Authors and Artifacts, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 93, Issue 1, 1 June 1993, Pages 155–178, https://doi.org/10.1093/arist.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  5.  12
    Deontic logic: introductory and systematic readings.Risto Hilpinen (ed.) - 1976 - Hingham, MA: Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Boston.
  6. Artifact.Risto Hilpinen - 1999 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  7. On artifacts and works of art.Risto Hilpinen - 1992 - Theoria 58 (1):58-82.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  8. New Studies in Deontic Logic: Norms, Actions, and the Foundations of Ethics.Risto Hilpinen (ed.) - 1981 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Wiley-Blackwell.
    The present volume is a sequel to Deontic Logic: Introductory and Systematic Readings : its purpose is to offer a view of some of the main directions of research in contemporary deontic logic. Most of the articles included in Introductory and Systematic Readings represent what may be called the standard modal approach to deontic logic, in which de on tic logic is treated as a branch of modal logic, and the normative concepts of obligation, permission and prohibition are regarded as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  9.  20
    Lennart Åqvist in Memoriam.Åke Frändberg, Risto Hilpinen & Lars Lindahl - 2019 - Theoria 85 (5):345-349.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Deontic Logic: Introductory and Systematic Readings.Risto Hilpinen - 1976 - Critica 8 (23):118-125.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  11.  13
    Good reason: essays dedicated to Risto Hilpinen.Risto Hilpinen, Olli Koistinen & Juha Räikkä (eds.) - 1993 - Turku: Turun yliopisto.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  4
    Rules of acceptance and inductive logic.Risto Hilpinen - 1968 - Amsterdam: North-Holland Pub. Co..
  13. Juristische Logik, Rationalität Und Irrationalität Im Recht = Juristic Logic, Rationality and Irrationality in Law.André Jean Arnaud, Risto Hilpinen & Roberto José Vernengo - 1985
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Juristische Logik, Rationalität und Irrationalität im Recht.André Jean Arnaud, Risto Hilpinen, Jerzy Wróblewski & Roberto José Vernengo (eds.) - 1985 - Berlin: Duncker Und Humblot.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Knowledge and conditionals.Risto Hilpinen - 1988 - Philosophical Perspectives 2:157-182.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  16.  67
    On C. S. Peirce’s Theory of the Proposition.Risto Hilpinen - 1982 - The Monist 65 (2):182-188.
    Peirce discusses the nature and structure of propositions in several manuscripts written in the 1890’s and during the first decade of this century. In this paper I shall outline the main features of Peirce’s theory of the proposition, especially his account of what may be called indeterminate indices in propositions.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  17.  47
    On C. S. Peirce’s Theory of the Proposition.Risto Hilpinen - 1982 - The Monist 65 (2):182 - 188.
    Peirce discusses the nature and structure of propositions in several manuscripts written in the 1890’s and during the first decade of this century. In this paper I shall outline the main features of Peirce’s theory of the proposition, especially his account of what may be called indeterminate indices in propositions.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  18. Rules of Acceptance and Inductive Logic.Risto Hilpinen - 1971 - Synthese 22 (3-4):482-487.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  19.  83
    Knowing that one knows and the classical definition of knowledge.Risto Hilpinen - 1970 - Synthese 21 (2):109 - 132.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  20. New Studies in Deontic Logic. Norms, Actions and Foundations of Ethics.Risto Hilpinen - 1983 - Studia Logica 42 (1):110-111.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  21.  32
    On Peirce's Philosophical Logic: Propositions and Their Objects.Risto Hilpinen - 1992 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 28 (3):467 - 488.
  22. Peirce on language and reference.Risto Hilpinen - 1995 - In Kenneth Laine Ketner (ed.), Peirce and Contemporary Thought: Philosophical Inquiries. Fordham University Press. pp. 272--303.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  23.  78
    Belief Systems as Artifacts.Risto Hilpinen - 1995 - The Monist 78 (2):136-155.
    Many philosophers have used the concept of belief system or some related notion as a basic tool of epistemological discussion and analysis. A belief system is a set of propositions or statements which represents a person’s doxastic state or credal state in a certain situation; it consists of the propositions which the person either explicitly or implicitly accepts in the situation. One of the many concerns of epistemologists is to attempt to formulate general “conditions of rationality” for belief systems. I (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  24.  84
    Carnap's new system of inductive logic.Risto Hilpinen - 1973 - Synthese 25 (3-4):307 - 333.
  25.  87
    2012 Presidential Address: Types and Tokens: On the Identity and Meaning of Names and Other Words.Risto Hilpinen - 2012 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 48 (3):259-284.
    Charles S. Peirce introduces the distinction between a token and a type into semiotics and philosophy by using as an example two ways of individuating words:(P1) A common mode of estimating the amount of matter in a MS. or printed book is to count the number of words. There will ordinarily be about twenty the's on a page, and of course they count as twenty words. In another sense of the word "word," however, there is but one word "the" in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26.  16
    Deontic Logic.Risto Hilpinen - 2017 - In Lou Goble (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 159–182.
    Deontic logic is an area of logic which investigates normative concepts, systems of norms, and normative reasoning. The word ‘deontic’ is derived from the Greek expression ‘déon’, which means ‘what is binding’ or ‘proper’. Thus, Jeremy Bentham used the word ‘deontology’ for “the science of morality,” and the Austrian philosopher Ernst Mally, who developed in the 1920s a system of the “fundamental principles the logic of ought,” called his theory ‘Deontik’. Normative concepts include the concepts of obligation (ought), permission (may), (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  23
    Peirce's logic.Risto Hilpinen - 2004 - In Dov M. Gabbay, John Woods & Akihiro Kanamori (eds.), Handbook of the History of Logic. Elsevier. pp. 3--611.
  28. On a pragmatic theory of meaning and knowledge.Risto Hilpinen - 2004 - Cognitio 5 (2):150.
    : According to C. S. Peirce, there are two ways of explaining what a sign means, namely, a definition and a precept. A precept tells the interpreters of a sign what the sign means by prescribing what they have to do in order to find or become acquainted with an object of the sign. A precept for a concept specifies how an interpreter can determine whether the concept is applicable to a given situation or object.Peirce accepted the scholastic definition of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29.  26
    On the conditions of causality.Risto Hilpinen - 1973 - Philosophical Studies 24 (6):386 - 391.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30.  33
    On the immediate and dynamical interpretants and objects of signs.Risto Hilpinen - 2019 - Semiotica 2019 (228):91-101.
    In his semiotic system Peirce distinguished between two interpretants and two objects of a sign: an immediate and a dynamical interpretant, and an immediate and a dynamical object. It is argued that Peirce’s immediate object can be interpreted a qua-object which has the dynamical object as its basis, and the dynamical interpretant consists of an interpreter’s conception of the object of the sign. Peirce semiotic system is compared with the accounts given by Frege, Husserl, Meinong, and the Stoics.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  61
    Peirce, Goodman and the Aesthetic Sign.Risto Hilpinen - 1990 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 37 (1):177-184.
    Expressions of the form "s represents an F", "s represents t as G", and "s represents an F as G" are analysed by means of C. S. Peirce's and Nelson Goodman's semiotic theories, and these theories are compared with each other. It is argued that Peirce's concept of interpretant provides a plausible account of what Goodman calls the exemplification features of aesthetic signs (works of art).
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  8
    Peirce, Goodman and the Aesthetic Sign.Risto Hilpinen - 1990 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 37 (1):177-184.
    Expressions of the form "s represents an F", "s represents t as G", and "s represents an F as G" are analysed by means of C. S. Peirce's and Nelson Goodman's semiotic theories, and these theories are compared with each other. It is argued that Peirce's concept of interpretant provides a plausible account of what Goodman calls the exemplification features of aesthetic signs (works of art).
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33. The Semantics of Questions and the Theory of Inquiry.Risto Hilpinen - 1986 - Logique Et Analyse 29 (116):523-539.
  34.  90
    On Practical Abduction.Risto Hilpinen - 2007 - Theoria 73 (3):207-220.
    In this paper practical reasoning is understood in the Aristotelian sense as reasoning leading to action or to an intention to do something. Georg Henrik von Wright and a number of other philosophers have tried to assimilate certain forms of such reasoning to deductive reasoning. Many examples of practical reasoning, including some examples given by Aristotle, do not fit a deductive or quasi‐deductive model. It is argued that instances of good practical reasoning often resemble abductive rather than deductive or inductive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  46
    Relational hypotheses and inductive inference.Risto Hilpinen - 1971 - Synthese 23 (2-3):266 - 286.
    This paper discusses the probabilities of inductive generalizations in languages containing two-place predicates. The depth of the sentences considered here is restricted to two, that is, they contain at most two layers of quantifiers. The analysis of relational hypotheses presented below is based on the theory of distributive normal forms in first-order logic. The main purpose of this paper is not to present methods of calculating unique probability-values for various generalizations, but rather to clarify the general conceptual situation and concentrate (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  80
    Conception, sense, and reference in Peircean semiotics.Risto Hilpinen - 2015 - Synthese 192 (4):1-28.
    In his Logical Investigations Edmund Husserl criticizes John Stuart Mill’s account of meaning as connotation, especially Mill’s failure to separate the distinction between connotative and non-connotative names from the distinction between the meaningful and the meaningless. According to Husserl, both connotative and non-connotative names have meaning or “signification”, that is, what Gottlob Frege calls the sense (“Sinn”) of an expression. The distinction between connotative and non-connotative names is a distinction between two kinds of meaning (or sense), attributive and non-attributive meaning (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. Norms, Normative Utterances, and Normative Propositions.Risto Hilpinen - 2006 - Análisis Filosófico 26 (2).
    It is argued that the distinction between the normative and the descriptive interpretation of norm sentences can be regarded as a distinction between two kinds of utterances. A norm or a directive has as its content a normative proposition. A normative utterance of a normative proposition in appropriate circumstances makes the proposition true, and an assertive utterance has as its truth-maker the norm system to which it refers. This account of norms, norm-contents, and utterances of norm sentences solves Jørgensen’s problem: (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  44
    A note on necessary-and-sufficient causes.Risto Hilpinen - 1974 - Philosophical Studies 26 (5-6):447 - 448.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  77
    Rules of acceptance, indices of lawlikeness, and singular inductive inference: Reply to a critical discussion.Risto Hilpinen & Jaakko Hintikka - 1971 - Philosophy of Science 38 (2):303-307.
  40. some Remarks On Self-deception: Mele, Moore And Lakatos.Risto Hilpinen - 2002 - Florida Philosophical Review 2 (1):82-97.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  4
    Review of Risto Hilpinen: Rationality in Science: Studies in the Foundations of Science and Ethics[REVIEW]Risto Hilpinen - 1982 - Ethics 93 (1):191-192.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  68
    Notes on The Cambridge Companion to Peirce.Risto Hilpinen - 2005 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 41 (4):740-761.
  43. Schlick on the Foundations of Knowledge.Risto Hilpinen - 1982 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 16 (1):63-78.
    This paper outlines the main features of the conception of empirical knowledge presented by Moritz Schlick in his paper 'Über das Fundament der Erkenntnis', and contains a detaüed analysis of Schlick's concept of "Konstatierung". It is argued that in spite of its basically foundationalist appearance, Schlick's theory resembles in important respects contemporary coherence theories of knowledge.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  11
    Agent, Language, and the Structure of the World: Essays Presented to Hector-Neri Castaneda, with His Replies.Risto Hilpinen & James E. Tomberlin - 1988 - Noûs 22 (2):307.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  4
    Deontic, Epistemic, and Temporal Modal Logics.Risto Hilpinen - 2006 - In Dale Jacquette (ed.), A Companion to Philosophical Logic. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 491–509.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Modal Concepts The Semantics of Modalities and Systems of Modal Logic Modality and Quantification Deontic, Epistemic, and Temporal Modalities Epistemic Logic Deontic Logic Temporal Frames Conditional Obligations and Rules of Detachment.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Editorial Note.Risto Hilpinen - 1971 - Synthese 23 (2/3):347.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  22
    Inquiry, argumentation and knowledge.Risto Hilpinen - 1991 - In André Fuhrmann & Michael Morreau (eds.), The Logic of Theory Change. Springer. pp. 1--18.
  48.  26
    International union of history and philosophy of science division of logic, methodology and philosophy of science bulletin no. 11.Risto Hilpinen - 1987 - Studia Logica 46 (1):111-112.
  49.  42
    International union of history and philosophy of science division of logic, methodology and philosophy of science bulletin no. 10.Risto Hilpinen - 1986 - Synthese 67 (2):381-382.
  50.  54
    International union of history and philosophy of science; division of logic, methodology and philosophy of science bulletin no. 14.Risto Hilpinen - 1990 - Synthese 85 (1):179-183.
1 — 50 / 232