Results for 'Donald W. Livingston'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. David Hume.Donald W. Livingston - 2012 - In Thierry Baudet & Michiel Visser (eds.), Revolutionair verval en de conservatieve vooruitgang in de achttiende en negentiende eeuw. Amsterdam: Bakker.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  76
    Hume's philosophy of common life.Donald W. Livingston - 1984 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  3.  40
    Philosophical Melancholy and Delirium: Hume's Pathology of Philosophy.Donald W. Livingston - 1998 - University of Chicago Press.
    Here Donald Livingston traces this distinction through all of Hume's writings and reveals its relevance for contemporary discussion.
  4.  35
    Hume: a re-evaluation.Donald W. Livingston & James T. King (eds.) - 1976 - New York: Fordham University Press.
  5.  46
    A Sellarsian Hume?Donald W. Livingston - 1991 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 29 (2):281-290.
  6. Anscombe, Hume and Julius Caesar.Donald W. Livingston - 1974 - Analysis 35 (1):13 - 19.
  7.  21
    Good and bad shadow history of philosophy.Donald W. Livingston - 1993 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 31 (1):111-113.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  58
    On Hume's Conservatism.Donald W. Livingston - 1995 - Hume Studies 21 (2):151-164.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Studies Volume XXI, Number 2, November 1995, pp. 151-164 On Hume's Conservatism DONALD W. LIVINGSTON In Opinion and Reform in Hume's Political Philosophy,1 John Stewart seeks to establish two theses. The first is that Hume's philosophical skepticism does not entail political conservatism as many commentators have argued, and the second is that central to all of Hume's writings, but especially to the History and the Essays, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  30
    Hume on Ultimate Causation.Donald W. Livingston - 1971 - American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1):63 - 70.
  10. Amoral accounting of.Donald W. Livingston - 2002 - Journal of Libertarian Studies 16 (2):57-101.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  25
    Butler.Donald W. Livingston - 1988 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 26 (3):490-492.
  12.  49
    Hayek as Humean.Donald W. Livingston - 1991 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 5 (2):159-177.
    In his Hayek and Modern Liberalism, Chandran Kukathas claims that Hayek's political philosophy is fundamentally incoherent because it is heavily influenced from two incompatible directions: that of Hume and that of Kant. But in fact, the idiom in which Hayek's philosophy is cast is overwhelmingly Humean. Whatever difficulties Hayek's thought may contain, the incoherence Kukathas identifies is not one of them.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  8
    Hume as philosopher of society, politics, and history.Donald W. Livingston & Marie Martin (eds.) - 1991 - Rochester, N.Y.: University of Rochester Press.
    The idea of Hume as a philosopher of culture has only recently gained general acceptance; yet as far back as 1941 the Journal of the History of Ideas was publishing essays on Hume which reflected this aspect of his work. The essays selected for this volume range back as far as 1941, but they may be viewed as more timely than ever, given the recent interest in Hume as a philosopher of society, politics and history.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  36
    Hume on the Problem of Historical and Scientific Explanation.Donald W. Livingston - 1973 - New Scholasticism 47 (1):38-67.
  15. Lincoln Symbols.Donald W. Livingston - 2002 - Telos: Critical Theory of the Contemporary 2002 (122):156-168.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  41
    Theism and the Rationale of Hume’s Skepticism About Causation.Donald W. Livingston - 1985 - Idealistic Studies 15 (2):151-164.
    Hume is famous for having introduced a radical theory of the nature of causation. To say that A causes B is just to say that A is constantly conjoined with B and that experience of the conjunction determines the mind to expect the one on the appearance of the other. It was this theory that awoke Kant from his dogmatic slumbers and established Hume as a founding figure of the various forms of positivism that emerged from the nineteenth century. A. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  38
    The Deductive Requirement and the Problem of Explicating Historical Explanation.Donald W. Livingston - 1976 - Modern Schoolman 53 (3):265-276.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  27
    The Politics of Progress: The Origins and Development of the Commercial Republic, 1600-1835.Donald W. Livingston - 1991 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 29 (3):490-492.
  19.  7
    Liberty in Hume’s History of England.N. Capaldi & Donald W. Livingston (eds.) - 1990 - Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    LIBERTY IN HUME'S HISTORY OF ENGLAND In his own lifetime, Hume was feted by his admirers as a great historian, and even his enemies conceded that he was a controversial historian with whom one had to reckon. On the other hand, Hume failed to achieve positive recognition for his philosophical views. It was Hume's History of England that played an influential role in public policy debate during the eighteenth century in both Great Britain and in the United States. Hume's Hist01Y (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  35
    D. C. Stove, "Probability and Hume's Inductive Scepticism". [REVIEW]Donald W. Livingston - 1975 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 13 (3):413.
  21.  16
    David Hume. [REVIEW]Donald W. Livingston - 1979 - International Studies in Philosophy 11:227-228.
  22.  10
    David Hume. [REVIEW]Donald W. Livingston - 1979 - International Studies in Philosophy 11:227-228.
  23.  43
    Nicholas Capaldi, "Hume's Place in Moral Philosophy". [REVIEW]Donald W. Livingston - 1991 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 29 (4):682.
  24.  41
    Peter Jones, "Hume's Sentiments, Their Ciceronian and French Context". [REVIEW]Donald W. Livingston - 1984 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 22 (4):482.
  25.  2
    Terence Penelhum, "Butler". [REVIEW]Donald W. Livingston - 1988 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 26 (3):490.
  26. Donald W. Livingston, Hume's Philosophy of Common Life Reviewed by.Terence Penelhum - 1985 - Philosophy in Review 5 (10):459-461.
  27. Subjective Well-Being and Desire Satisfaction.Donald W. Bruckner - 2010 - Philosophical Papers 39 (1):1-28.
    There is a large literature in empirical psychology studying what psychologists call 'subjective well-being'. Only limited attention has been given to these results by philosophers who study what we call 'well-being'. In this paper, I assess the relevance of the empirical results to one philosophical theory of well-being, the desire satisfaction theory. According to the desire satisfaction theory, an individual's well-being is enhanced when her desires are satisfied. The empirical results, however, show that many of our desires are disappointed in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. Urban planning and ethics: a selected bibliography with special focus on Constantinos A. Doxiadis and H. Richard Niebuhr.Donald W. Huffman - 1974 - Monticello, Ill.: Council of Planning Librarians.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  20
    Opinion and Reform in Hume's Political Philosophy. [REVIEW]Donald Becker - 1994 - Review of Metaphysics 47 (3):641-642.
    Stewart's purpose is to show that Hume is not a political conservative, but is better understood as a liberal. The author is reacting against several recent works on Hume: David Miller's Philosophy and Ideology in Hume's Political Thought, Donald W. Livingston's Hume's Philosophy of Common Life, and Frederick G. Whelan's Order and Artifice in Hume's Political Philosophy. These "all share, with variations, the nineteenth-century view that Hume's epistemology led him to conservatism". Stewart acknowledges that the term "conservative" is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  6
    How brain arousal mechanisms work: paths toward consciousness.Donald W. Pfaff - 2019 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    A succinct, neurobiological explanation of the pathways that 'wake up the brain' from deep anesthesia, sleep and brain injury.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  29
    Donald W. Livingston, "Hume's Philosophy of Common Life". [REVIEW]David Fate Norton - 1987 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 25 (2):300.
  32. Donald W. Livingston, Hume's Philosophy of Common Life. [REVIEW]Terence Penelhum - 1985 - Philosophy in Review 5:459-461.
  33.  40
    An ethic for enemies: forgiveness in politics.Donald W. Shriver - 1995 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Our century has witnessed violence on an unprecedented scale, in wars that have torn deep into the fabric of national and international life. And as we can see in the recent strife in Bosnia, genocide in Rwanda, and the ongoing struggle to control nuclear weaponry, ancient enmities continue to threaten the lives of masses of human beings. As never before, the question is urgent and practical: How can nations--or ethnic groups, or races--after long, bitter struggles, learn to live side by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  34.  8
    Donald W. Livingston and James T. King, eds., "Hume: A Re-evaluation". [REVIEW]T. E. Jessop - 1979 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 17 (1):101.
  35.  19
    Moderate Realism and Its Logic.Donald W. Mertz - 1996 - Yale University Press.
    Applying the rules and systems of mathematics and logic to instance ontology, this work argues for the validity and problem-solving capacities of instance ontology, and associates it with a version of the realist position which is named by the author as moderate realism.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  36. The Experience of Landscape.Donald W. Crawford - 1976 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 34 (3):367-369.
  37. Strict Vegetarianism is Immoral.Donald W. Bruckner - 2015 - In Ben Bramble & Fischer Bob (eds.), The Moral Complexities of Eating Meat. Oxford University Press. pp. 30-47.
    The most popular and convincing arguments for the claim that vegetarianism is morally obligatory focus on the extensive, unnecessary harm done to animals and to the environment by raising animals industrially in confinement conditions (factory farming). I outline the strongest versions of these arguments. I grant that it follows from their central premises that purchasing and consuming factoryfarmed meat is immoral. The arguments fail, however, to establish that strict vegetarianism is obligatory because they falsely assume that eating vegetables is the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  38.  28
    Mechanisms underlying an ability to behave ethically.Donald W. Pfaff, Martin Kavaliers & Elena Choleris - 2008 - American Journal of Bioethics 8 (5):10 – 19.
    Cognitive neuroscientists have anticipated the union of neural and behavioral science with ethics (Gazzaniga 2005). The identification of an ethical rule—the dictum that we should treat others in the manner in which we would like to be treated—apparently widespread among human societies suggests a dependence on fundamental human brain mechanisms. Now, studies of neural and molecular mechanisms that underlie the feeling of fear suggest how this form of ethical behavior is produced. Counterintuitively, a new theory presented here states that it (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  39. A Key to Whitehead's Process and Reality.Donald W. Sherburne - 1966 - University of Chicago Press.
    Whitehead's magnum opus is as important as it is difficult. It is the only work in which his metaphysical ideas are stated systematically and completely, and his metaphysics are the heart of his philosophical system as a whole.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  40.  50
    Gegenstandstheoretische Grundlagen der Logik und Logistik.Donald W. Fisher - 1914 - Philosophical Review 23 (4):470-471.
  41. In defense of adaptive preferences.Donald W. Bruckner - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 142 (3):307 - 324.
    An adaptive preference is a preference that is regimented in response to an agent’s set of feasible options. The fabled fox in the sour grapes story undergoes an adaptive preference change. I consider adaptive preferences more broadly, to include adaptive preference formation as well. I argue that many adaptive preferences that other philosophers have cast out as irrational sour-grapes-like preferences are actually fully rational preferences worthy of pursuit. I offer a means of distinguishing rational and worthy adaptive preferences from irrational (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  42.  25
    Institutional Corruption of Pharmaceuticals and the Myth of Safe and Effective Drugs.Donald W. Light, Joel Lexchin & Jonathan J. Darrow - 2013 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 41 (3):590-600.
    Institutional corruption is a normative concept of growing importance that embodies the systemic dependencies and informal practices that distort an institution’s societal mission. An extensive range of studies and lawsuits already documents strategies by which pharmaceutical companies hide, ignore, or misrepresent evidence about new drugs; distort the medical literature; and misrepresent products to prescribing physicians. We focus on the consequences for patients: millions of adverse reactions. After defining institutional corruption, we focus on evidence that it lies behind the epidemic of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  43.  55
    Human and Animal Well‐Being.Donald W. Bruckner - 2021 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 102 (3):393-412.
    There is almost no theoretical discussion of non‐human animal well‐being in the philosophical literature on well‐being. To begin to rectify this, I develop a desire satisfaction theory of well‐being for animals. I contrast this theory with my desire theory of well‐being for humans, according to which a human benefits from satisfying desires for which she can offer reasons. I consider objections. The most important are (1) Eden Lin's claim that the correct theory of well‐being cannot vary across different welfare subjects (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  44.  59
    Institutional Corruption of Pharmaceuticals and the Myth of Safe and Effective Drugs.Donald W. Light, Joel Lexchin & Jonathan J. Darrow - 2013 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 41 (3):590-600.
    Over the past 35 years, patients have suffered from a largely hidden epidemic of side effects from drugs that usually have few offsetting benefits. The pharmaceutical industry has corrupted the practice of medicine through its influence over what drugs are developed, how they are tested, and how medical knowledge is created. Since 1906, heavy commercial influence has compromised congressional legislation to protect the public from unsafe drugs. The authorization of user fees in 1992 has turned drug companies into the FDA's (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  45. Present Desire Satisfaction and Past Well-Being.Donald W. Bruckner - 2013 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91 (1):15 - 29.
    One version of the desire satisfaction theory of well-being (i.e., welfare, or what is good for one) holds that only the satisfaction of one's present desires for present states of affairs can affect one's well-being. So if I desire fame today and become famous tomorrow, my well-being is positively affected onlyif tomorrow, when I am famous, I still desire to be famous. Call this the present desire satisfaction theory of well-being. I argue, contrary to this theory, that the satisfaction of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  46. Kant's aesthetic theory.Donald W. Crawford - 1974 - [Madison]: University of Wisconsin Press.
    Immanuel Kant was a German philosopher. He is a central figure of modern philosophy, and set the terms by which all subsequent thinkers have had to grapple. He argued that human perception structures natural laws, and that reason is the source of morality. His thought continues to hold a major influence in contemporary thought, especially in fields such as metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, political philosophy, and aesthetics.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  47.  7
    Durable secondary reinforcement: Method and theory.Donald W. Zimmerman - 1957 - Psychological Review 64 (6, Pt.1):373-383.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. A Short History of Buddhism.Donald W. Mitchell - 1982 - Philosophy East and West 32 (1):109-111.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  49. Against the Tedium of Immortality.Donald W. Bruckner - 2012 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 20 (5):623-644.
    In a well-known paper, Bernard Williams argues that an immortal life would not be worth living, for it would necessarily become boring. I examine the implications for the boredom thesis of three human traits that have received insufficient attention in the literature on Williams’ paper. First, human memory decays, so humans would be entertained and driven by things that they experienced long before but had forgotten. Second, even if memory does not decay to the extent necessary to ward off boredom, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  50.  37
    Philosophy and animal welfare science.Donald W. Bruckner - 2019 - Philosophy Compass 14 (10):e12626.
    Although human well-being is a topic of much contemporary philosophical discussion, there has been comparatively little theoretical discussion in philosophy of (nonhuman) animal well-being. Animal welfare science is a well-established scientific discipline that studies animal well-being from an empirical standpoint. This article examines parts of this literature that may be relevant to philosophical treatments of animal well-being and to other philosophical issues. First, I explain the dominant conceptions of well-being in animal welfare science and survey some debates in that literature (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000