Results for 'Saul Fisher'

(not author) ( search as author name )
998 found
Order:
  1.  10
    On Guyer’s Vitruvian Normativity.Saul Fisher - 2024 - Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics 61 (1):81-89.
    A critical note on Paul Guyer’s A Philosopher Looks at Architecture (2021). In his book, Paul Guyer proposes that the Vitruvian triad of venustas, utilitas, and firmitas represents central goals and normative values of architecture – ideals that architects should realize and success criteria regarding their realization – that persist through time, place, cultural settings, and other contextual parameters. Indeed, the triad presents sufficiently abstract goals that many disparate views in architectural theory may be subsumed under the triad as distinctive (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  18
    Architectural Responsibilities and the Right to a City.Saul Fisher - 2023 - Architecture Philosophy 6 (1/2):63-82.
    I sketch a version of the right to the city (RTTC) that is (a) feasible, (b) generic, and so (c) broadly amenable to many of its adherents. This right, I suggest, entails special sorts of responsibilities or obligations for architects and others tending to our built environment and the spaces—especially public space—so structured and defined. Along the way, I provide a brief account of some historical motivations for embracing the right to the city, as well as reasons for endorsing my (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  14
    Architecture, Buildings, and Political Ends.Saul Fisher - 2023 - Aesthetic Investigations 6 (1):19-32.
    It is not infrequently heard in architectural circles that architecture is an inherently political enterprise and pursuit, such that build structures are, correspondingly, inherently political objects. But does architecture, by its nature as practice or artifact, universally serve political ends? Taking ends of something X to be political iff X serves the projection of power by state or government, or advances policy-making, ideologies, or the body politic, it may be thought that AP1. Architecture, in its products, always serves political ends. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Philosophy of Architecture.Saul Fisher - 2015 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Central issues in philosophy of architecture include foundational matters regarding the nature of: (1) architecture as an artform, design medium, or other product or practice; (2) architectural objects—what sorts of things they are; how they differ from other sorts of objects; and how we define the range of such objects; (3) special architectural properties, like the standard trio of structural integrity (firmitas), beauty, and utility—or space, light, and form; and ways they might be special to architecture; (4) architectural types—how to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  5.  33
    Pierre Gassendi's Philosophy And Science: Atomism for Empiricists.Saul Fisher - 2005 - Leiden, Netherlands: Brill.
    This look at Gassendi’s philosophy and science illuminates his contributions to early modern thought and to the broader history of philosophy of science. Two keys to his thought are his novel picture of acquiring and judging empirical belief, and his liberal account of criteria for counting empirical beliefs as parts of warranted physical theories. By viewing his philosophical and scientific pursuits as part of one and the same project, Gassendi’s arguments on behalf of atomism can be fruitfully explained as licensed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6.  18
    Lifespans of Built Structures, Narrativity, and Conservation: A Critical Note.Saul Fisher - 2020 - Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics (1):93-103.
    A critical note on Peter Lamarque and Nigel Walter’s ‘The Application of Narrative to the Conservation of Historic Buildings’.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  42
    Pierre gassendi.Saul Fisher - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Pierre Gassendi (b. 1592, d. 1655) was a French philosopher, scientific chronicler, observer, and experimentalist, scholar of ancient texts and debates, and active participant in contemporary deliberations of the first half of the seventeenth century. His significance in early modern thought has in recent years been rediscovered and explored, towards a better understanding of the dawn of modern empiricism, the mechanical philosophy, and relations of modern philosophy to ancient and medieval discussions. Through an arch-empiricism—tempered by adherence to key elements of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  15
    Hip: Personal Style and Aesthetic Property.Saul Fisher - 2023 - Bloomsbury Contemporary Aesthetics Case Studies and Articles.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  8
    Architecture.Saul Fisher - 2023 - In James Harold (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Ethics and Art. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. pp. 456-471.
    Ethical issues of architecture arise relative to its processes of creation, its reception and use, and its maintenance and life cycle—all as a function of architecture’s aesthetic or artistic character and values, though not exclusively so. While autonomism and moralism in architecture are much debated, the focus is generally on architecture as art, to the neglect of architectural aesthetics beyond architecture as art. Moreover, as an artform deeply integrated with other, nonart pursuits and domains, architecture generates more complex ethical issues (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  75
    How to Think about the Ethics of Architecture.Saul Fisher - 2000 - In Warwick Fox (ed.), Ethics and the Built Environment. London, UK: pp. 170-182.
    Philosophical ethicists have not yet fully explored, or even mapped out, the problems posed by architectural practice. While some have attempted such explorations, their accounts suffer assorted philosophical deficits, and generally miss the aim of reasoned moral analysis. I believe that the most fruitful attempts to think about such issues in philosophical terms—in lieu of an analytical architectural ethics—are found in the body of architectural law. There we may glimpse some promising philosophical considerations pertaining to such matters as intellectual property, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  74
    Architectural notation and computer aided design.Saul Fisher - 2000 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 58 (3):273-289.
    In his Languages of Art, Nelson Goodman proposes a theory of artistic notation that includes foundational requirements for any system of symbols we might use to specify and communicate the features of an artwork, in architecture or any other art form. Goodmans' theory usefully explains how notation can reveal linguistic-like phenomena of various art forms. But not all art forms can enjoy benefits of a full-blown notational system, in Goodman's view, and he suggests that architecture's symbol systems fall short in (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  36
    Early modern philosophy and biological thought.Saul Fisher - 2003 - Perspectives on Science 11 (4):373-377.
    Presents several articles on the modern philosophy and biological perspective on life science.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  41
    Gassendi's atomist account of generation and heredity in plants and animals.Saul Fisher - 2003 - Perspectives on Science 11 (4):484-512.
    In his accounts of plant and animal generation Pierre Gassendi offers a mechanist story of how organisms create offspring to whom they pass on their traits. Development of the new organism is directed by a material “soul” or animula bearing ontogenetic information. Where reproduction is sexual, two sets of material semina and corresponding animulae meet and jointly determine the division, differentiation, and development of matter in the new organism. The determination of inherited traits requires a means of combining or choosing (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  3
    Gassendi and Epicureanism.Saul Fisher - 2023 - In Delphine Bellis, Daniel Garber & Carla Rita Palmerino (eds.), Pierre Gassendi: Humanism, Science, and the Birth of Modern Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 106-143.
    As the premier early modern advocate of an Epicurean alternative to the prevailing neo-Scholastic framework of Aristotelianism, Pierre Gassendi promoted not only ancient but also innovative reasoning on behalf of atomism, probabilism, empiricism, psychological hedonism, social contractarianism, and a range of other stances associated with the philosophy of the Garden. Much commentary has focused on the extent to which Gassendi ‘baptizes’ Epicurean thought. Beyond this aspect of his Epicureanism are questions as to whether, and how, Gassendi is true to core (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  28
    Gassendi et l’Hypothèse dans la Méthode Scientifique.Saul Fisher - 2008 - In Sylvie Taussig (ed.), Gassendi et la modernité. Turnhout, Belgium: pp. 399-425.
    Aucune méthode d'hypothèse et de raisonnement hypothétique en science ne peut être examinée dc façon critique sans que soit résolue au préalable la question de ce qui sert d'hypothèse. D'un point de vue très général, des éléments très différents peuvent servir à constituer la partie hypothétique ou conjecturale de la science. Du temps de Gassendi, il était possible de recourir à des entités hypothétiques tels les tourbillons cartésiens, à de généralisations idéalisées de phénomènes telle la loi de la chute libre, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  17
    Open Technologies and Resources for the Humanities – and Cooperative Consequences.Saul Fisher - 2006 - Arts and Humanities in Higher Education 5 (2):127-145.
    The proliferation of open technologies and content in higher education is motivated by broad embrace of a principle of sharing that is consonant with various contemporary economic, pedagogic and policy drivers.At the same time, open technologies and content present the possibility of a departure in the culture of humanities research and teaching.The open frameworks celebrate and facilitate collaborative and cooperative modes of working which are, to a degree, alien to a traditional ‘individualist’ conception of work in the Humanities. But such (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  2
    ‘Probabilist’ Deductive Inference in Gassendi’s Logic.Saul Fisher - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 8:58-64.
    In his Logic, Pierre Gassendi proposes that our inductive inferences lack the information we would need to be certain of the claims that they suggest. Not even deductivist inference can insure certainty about empirical claims because the experientially attained premises with which we adduce support for such claims are no greater than probable. While something is surely amiss in calling deductivist inference "probabilistic," it seems Gassendi has hit upon a now-familiar, sensible point—namely, the use of deductive reasoning in empirical contexts, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  26
    Ruins and Sham Ruins as Architectural Objects.Saul Fisher - 2019 - In Jeanette Bicknell, Jennifer Judkins & Carolyn Korsmeyer (eds.), Ruins, Monuments, and Memorials: Philosophical Perspectives on Artifacts and Memory. Taylor & Francis.
    The premium on authenticity attributed to aesthetic appreciation and judgment of ruins is unnecessary, even while valuable for engagement with ruins as historical objects. I contrast values we assign to architectural ruins and to nongenuine, sham ruins. Ruins are components of built past architectural objects; sham ruins are components of fantasy, unbuilt architectural objects. Taking architectural objects as abstractions realized or realizable as built objects, ruins and sham ruins alike are built instances of corresponding abstract objects. Sham ruins do not (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Science and Skepticism in the Seventeenth Century: The Atomism and Scientific Method of Pierre Gassendi.Saul Fisher - 1997 - Dissertation, City University of New York
    In this account of the philosophical and scientific pursuits of Pierre Gassendi , I challenge a traditional view which says that the inspiration, motivation, and demonstrative grounds for his physical atomism consist not in his empiricism but in his historicist commitments. Indeed, Gassendi suggests that it's a consequence of our best theory of knowledge and sound scientific method that we get evidence which warrants his microphysical theory. ;The primary novelty of his theory of empirical knowledge is his proposal, against the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  15
    The soul as vehicle for genetic information : Gassendi's account of inheritance.Saul Fisher - 2006 - In Justin E. H. Smith (ed.), The Problem of Animal Generation in Early Modern Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. pp. 103-123.
    Generation and heredity theories before early modern mechanist accounts might be faulted for numerous deficits. One might cite in this regard the failure to even attempt to explain how the inheritance of traits could occur, given what is known about the generation of new individuals. On the other hand, it would be hard to allow this as a true failure against the backdrop of a generation theory that poses form, and not matter, as the key to understanding the emergence of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  35
    Architecture and Philosophy of the City.Saul Fisher - 2019 - In Sharon M. Meagher, Samantha Noll & Joseph S. Biehl (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of the City. New York, NY, USA: pp. 131-142.
    The philosophy of architecture illuminates the nature of architectural objects, properties, and types—and the sorts of things they are; how we know about and judge architectural objects; and ethical and political considerations of architectural objects and practice. As intersects with the philosophy of the city, one set of questions focuses on (a) how the design process for built structures, and structures designed, relate to specifically urban contexts; (b) how our experience of built structures relates to urban contexts; and (c) how (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  22
    LEGO® Formalism in Architecture.Saul Fisher - 2017 - In Roy T. Cook & Sondra Bacharach (eds.), Lego and Philosophy: Constructing Reality Brick by Brick. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers. pp. 27-37.
    LEGO tells about not just LEGO architecture but architecture generally: its objects, its aesthetic properties, and how people judge them. To illustrate how thinking about LEGO can help people with such matters, this chapter considers some scenarios. These scenarios illustrate two very different ways of thinking about architecture. On the one hand, people might think architectural objects (more commonly, "works of architecture"), like buildings, bridges, and aqueducts, have forms that stand on their own, and which thereby do not depend on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Why is Architecture a “Social” Art?Saul Fisher - 2002 - In Carol C. Gould (ed.), Constructivism and Practice: Toward a Historical Epistemology. Lanham, MD, USA: pp. 193–203.
    Architecture is apparently unlike the other plastic arts in that we tend to attribute to it, nearly universally, a social nature. But what, if anything, makes architecture intrinsically ‘social’? There are two leading candidate reasons that architecture is considered as a social art: (S1) the aim of architecture, as determined or realized by architects’ underlying intentions, is to design shelter—a social need, and (S2) the practice of architecture requires interpersonal relations of a social nature; hence as an art form it (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  26
    When is Architecture Not Design?Saul Fisher - 2019 - Laocoonte: Revista de Estética y Teoría de Las Artes 1 (6):183-198.
    If there is nothing more to architecture than design –and to its attendant thinking processes–than design thinking, then core dimensions of the architectural enterprise from the perspective of (a) production and (b) use have no special character, over and above their counterparts in general design. Yet that does not appear to be true by the lights of architects or design specialists or the public at large. So what is it, at the core or periphery of the discipline or its objects, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  21
    Aestheticism: Deep Formalism and the Emergence of Modernist Aesthetics. [REVIEW]Saul Fisher - 2017 - British Journal of Aesthetics 57 (4):437-440.
    Surely amongst the most exciting and vindicating features of philosophy and criticism of art are the interactions that they have with the actual practices of art. The histories of art and current discussions about art are dotted with special moments in which philosophers or critics—from Ruskin through to Danto and beyond—become influenced, or were influenced by, the art of their times. More curious—and less common still—is the influence of philosophy of art on art criticism, or the other way around. The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  89
    Architectural theory: The vitruvian fallacy (volume I). [REVIEW]Saul Fisher - 2001 - British Journal of Aesthetics 41 (2):240-243.
  27.  16
    LISA T. SARASOHN, Gassendi's Ethics: Freedom in a Mechanistic Universe. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996. Pp. xii+236. ISBN 0-8014-2947-1. £35.50. [REVIEW]Saul Fisher - 1998 - British Journal for the History of Science 31 (3):361-375.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  30
    Letters to the Editor.Leemon McHenry, Frank B. Dilley, Saul Fisher, Richard Field, Michael Huemer & Bruce Wilshire - 2000 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 73 (5):169 - 186.
  29.  13
    Saul Fisher. Pierre Gassendi’s Philosophy and Science: Atomism for Empiricists. xxviii + 436 pp., bibl., index. Leiden: Brill Academic Publishers, 2005. $172.50. [REVIEW]Teresa Castelão‐Lawless - 2007 - Isis 98 (2):385-386.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Naming and Necessity: Lectures Given to the Princeton University Philosophy Colloquium.Saul A. Kripke - 1980 - Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Edited by Darragh Byrne & Max Kölbel.
  31. Abstracta and Abstraction in Trope Theory.A. R. J. Fisher - 2020 - Philosophical Papers 49 (1):41-67.
    Trope theory is a leading metaphysical theory in analytic ontology. One of its classic statements is found in the work of Donald C. Williams who argued that tropes qua abstract particulars are the very alphabet of being. The concept of an abstract particular has been repeatedly attacked in the literature. Opponents and proponents of trope theory alike have levelled their criticisms at the abstractness of tropes and the associated act of abstraction. In this paper I defend the concept of a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  32. Speaker’s Reference and Semantic Reference.Saul Kripke - 1977 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2 (1):255-276.
    am going to discuss some issues inspired by a well-known paper ofKeith Donnellan, "Reference and Definite Descriptions,”2 but the interest—to me—of the contrast mentioned in my title goes beyond Donnellan's paper: I think it is of considerable constructive as well as critical importance to the philosophy oflanguage. These applications, however, and even everything I might want to say relative to Donnellan’s paper, cannot be discussed in full here because of problems of length. Moreover, although I have a considerable interest in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   399 citations  
  33. Frege's Theory of Sense and Reference: Some Exegetical Notes.Saul A. Kripke - 2008 - Theoria 74 (3):181-218.
    Frege's theory of indirect contexts and the shift of sense and reference in these contexts has puzzled many. What can the hierarchy of indirect senses, doubly indirect senses, and so on, be? Donald Davidson gave a well-known 'unlearnability' argument against Frege's theory. The present paper argues that the key to Frege's theory lies in the fact that whenever a reference is specified (even though many senses determine a single reference), it is specified in a particular way, so that giving a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  34.  28
    Saint Thomas Aquinas and the Too-Many-Thinkers Problem.Kendall A. Fisher - 2020 - Quaestiones Disputatae 10 (2):106-124.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35. The Church-Turing ‘Thesis’ as a Special Corollary of Gödel’s Completeness Theorem.Saul A. Kripke - 2013 - In B. J. Copeland, C. Posy & O. Shagrir (eds.), Computability: Gödel, Turing, Church, and beyond. MIT Press.
    Traditionally, many writers, following Kleene (1952), thought of the Church-Turing thesis as unprovable by its nature but having various strong arguments in its favor, including Turing’s analysis of human computation. More recently, the beauty, power, and obvious fundamental importance of this analysis, what Turing (1936) calls “argument I,” has led some writers to give an almost exclusive emphasis on this argument as the unique justification for the Church-Turing thesis. In this chapter I advocate an alternative justification, essentially presupposed by Turing (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36. A Proof of Gamma.Saul A. Kripke - 2022 - In Katalin Bimbo (ed.), Essays in Honor of J. Michael Dunn. College Publications. pp. 261-265.
    This paper is dedicated to the memory of Mike Dunn. His untimely death is a loss not only to logic, computer science, and philosophy, but to all of us who knew and loved him. The paper gives an argument for closure under γ in standard systems of relevance logic (first proved by Meyer and Dunn 1969). For definiteness, I chose the example of R. The proof also applies to E and to the quantified systems RQ and EQ. The argument uses (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  3
    Schelling's mystical platonism: 1792-1802.Naomi Fisher - 2024 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    In this book, Naomi Fisher provides a cohesive interpretation of Schelling's philosophical work from 1792-1802 as a mystical Platonism. According to this interpretation, Schelling is guided by two overarching commitments during this time. First, Schelling is committed to mysticism regarding the absolute. That is, the absolute is ineffable; it cannot be described in conceptual terms. For this reason, it remains inferentially external to any given philosophical system. Second, Schelling is committed to a priority monism: All things are grounded in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. The elusive stallion.George Brandon Saul - 1948 - Prairie City, Ill.,: Decker Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  53
    Are generics especially pernicious?Jennifer Saul - 2023 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 66 (9):1689-1706.
    Against recent work by Haslanger and Leslie, I argue that we do not yet have good reason to think that we should single out generics about social groups out as peculiarly destructive, or that we should strive to eradicate them from our usage. Indeed, I suggest they continue to serve a very valuable purpose and we should not rush to condemn them.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  40.  18
    Kant's Explanatory Natural History.Mark Fisher - 2007 - In Philippe Huneman (ed.), Understanding purpose: Kant and the philosophy of biology. Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Press. pp. 8--101.
  41. Did Clinton say something false?J. M. Saul - 2000 - Analysis 60 (3):255-257.
  42. Introduction: the importance of properties.A. R. J. Fisher & Anna-Sofia Maurin - 2024 - In A. R. J. Fisher & Anna-Sofia Maurin (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Properties. London: Routledge.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  6
    Elämän onnesta.Saul Nieminen - 1984 - [Espoo]: Weilin + Göös.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  12
    Editorial Overview.Erik Fisher - 2011 - Science and Engineering Ethics 17 (4):607-620.
    Science policy mandates across the industrialized world insinuate more active roles for publics, their earlier participation in policy decisions, and expanded notions of science and technology governance. In response to these policies, engaged scholars in science studies have sought to design and conduct exercises aimed at better attuning science to its public contexts. As demand increases for innovative and potentially democratic forms of public engagement with science and technology, so also do the prospects for insights from science studies to contribute (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  45.  51
    Implicit Bias and Philosophy, Volume 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology.Michael Brownstein & Jennifer Mather Saul (eds.) - 2016 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    At the University of Sheffield during 2011 and 2012, a leading group of philosophers, psychologists, and others gathered to explore the nature and significance of implicit bias. The two volumes of Implicit Bias and Philosophy emerge from these workshops. Each volume philosophically examines core areas of psychological research on implicit bias as well as the ramifications of implicit bias for core areas of philosophy. Volume I: Metaphysics and Epistemology is comprised of two parts: “The Nature of Implicit Attitudes, Implicit Bias, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  46.  13
    The Aesthetic Exception: Essays on Art, Theatre, and Politics.Tony Fisher - 2023 - Manchester University Press.
    The aesthetic exception theorises anew the relation between art and politics. It challenges critical trends that discount the role of aesthetic autonomy, to impulsively reassert art as an effective form of social engagement. But it equally challenges those on the flipside of the efficacy debate, who insist that art's politics is limited to a recondite space of 'autonomous resistance'. The book shows how each side of the efficacy debate overlooks art's exceptional status and its social mediations. Mobilising philosophy and cultural (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. What is said and psychological reality; Grice's project and relevance theorists' criticisms.Jennifer M. Saul - 2002 - Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (3):347-372.
    One of the most important aspects of Grice’s theory of conversation is the drawing of a borderline between what is said and what is implic- ated. Grice’s views concerning this borderline have been strongly and influentially criticised by relevance theorists. In particular, it has become increasingly widely accepted that Grice’s notion of what is said is too lim- ited, and that pragmatics has a far larger role to play in determining what is said than Grice would have allowed. (See for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  48.  6
    Capitalist Realism: Is There No Alternative?Mark Fisher - 2009 - Zero Books.
    After 1989, capitalism has successfully presented itself as the only realistic political-economic system - a situation that the bank crisis of 2008, far from ending, actually compounded. The book analyses the development and principal features of this capitalist realism as a lived ideological framework. Using examples from politics, films, fiction, work and education, it argues that capitalist realism colours all areas of contemporary experience. But it will also show that, because of a number of inconsistencies and glitches internal to the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  49.  21
    Catholic bioethics for a new millennium.Anthony Fisher - 2012 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Can the Hippocratic and Judeo-Christian traditions be synthesized with contemporary thought about practical reason, virtue and community to provide real-life answers to the dilemmas of healthcare today? Bishop Anthony Fisher discusses conscience, relationships and law in relation to the modern-day controversies surrounding stem cell research, abortion, transplants, artificial feeding and euthanasia, using case studies to offer insight and illumination. What emerges is a reason-based bioethics for the twenty-first century; a bioethics that treats faith and reason with equal seriousness, that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50. Wittgenstein on rules and private language: an elementary exposition.Saul A. Kripke - 1982 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    In this book Saul Kripke brings his powerful philosophical intelligence to bear on Wittgenstein's analysis of the notion of following a rule.
1 — 50 / 998