Results for 'Elizabeth S. Belfiore'

999 found
Order:
  1.  13
    Tragic Pleasures: Aristotle on Plot and Emotion.Elizabeth S. Belfiore - 1992
    Of other ancient writers, call into question the traditional view that katharsis in the Poetics is a homeopathic process - one in which pity and fear affect emotions like themselves. She maintains, instead, that Aristotle considered katharsis to be an allopathic process in which pity and fear purge the soul of shameless, antisocial, and aggressive emotions. While exploring katharsis, Tragic Pleasures analyzes the closely related question of how the Poetics treats the.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  2.  78
    Socrates' Daimonic Art: Love for Wisdom in Four Platonic Dialogues.Elizabeth S. Belfiore - 2012 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Despite increasing interest in the figure of Socrates and in love in ancient Greece, no recent monograph studies these topics in all four of Plato's dialogues on love and friendship. This book provides important new insights into these subjects by examining Plato's characterization of Socrates in Symposium, Phaedrus, Lysis and the often neglected Alcibiades I. It focuses on the specific ways in which the philosopher searches for wisdom together with his young interlocutors, using an art that is 'erotic', not in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  3.  65
    Dancing with the Gods: The Myth of the Chariot in Plato's Phaedrus.Elizabeth S. Belfiore - 2006 - American Journal of Philology 127 (2):185-217.
  4.  22
    The Emotions of the Ancient Greeks: Studies in Aristotle and Classical Literature (review).Elizabeth S. Belfiore - 2007 - Classical World: A Quarterly Journal on Antiquity 101 (1):106-107.
  5.  68
    Plato's Greatest Accusation against Poetry.Elizabeth Belfiore - 1983 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 13 (sup1):39-62.
  6. A theory of imitation in Plato's `Republic'.Elizabeth Belfiore - 2006 - In Andrew Laird (ed.), Ancient Literary Criticism. Oxford University Press.
  7.  85
    Wine and Catharsis_ of the Emotions in Plato's _Laws.Elizabeth Belfiore - 1986 - Classical Quarterly 36 (02):421-.
    Plato's views on tragedy depend in large part on his views about the ethical consequences of emotional arousal. In the Republic, Plato treats the desires we feel in everyday life to weep and feel pity as appetites exactly like those for food or sex, whose satisfactions are ‘replenishments’. Physical desire is not reprehensible in itself, but is simply non-rational, not identical with reason but capable of being brought into agreement with it. Some desires, like that for simple and wholesome food, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8. Plato's Greatest Accusation against Poetry.Elizabeth Belfiore - 1983 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 9:39.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9. Family Friendship in Aristotle’s Ethics.Elizabeth Belfiore - 2001 - Ancient Philosophy 21 (1):113-132.
  10.  29
    Wine and Catharsis_ of the Emotions in Plato's _Laws.Elizabeth Belfiore - 1986 - Classical Quarterly 36 (2):421-437.
    Plato's views on tragedy depend in large part on his views about the ethical consequences of emotional arousal. In theRepublic, Plato treats the desires we feel in everyday life to weep and feel pity as appetites exactly like those for food or sex, whose satisfactions are ‘replenishments’. Physical desire is not reprehensible in itself, but is simplynon-rational, not identical with reason but capable of being brought into agreement with it. Some desires, like that for simple and wholesome food, are in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11.  70
    Pleasure, Tragedy and Aristotelian Psychology.Elizabeth Belfiore - 1985 - Classical Quarterly 35 (02):349-.
    Aristotle's Rhetoric defines fear as a kind of pain or disturbance and pity as a kind of pain . In his Poetics, however, pity and fear are associated with pleasure: ‘ The poet must provide the pleasure that comes from pity and fear by means of imitation’ . The question of the relationship between pleasure and pain in Aristotle's aesthetics has been studied primarily in connection with catharsis. Catharsis, however, raises more problems than it solves. Aristotle says nothing at all (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12.  34
    Pleasure, Tragedy and Aristotelian Psychology.Elizabeth Belfiore - 1985 - Classical Quarterly 35 (2):349-361.
    Aristotle'sRhetoricdefines fear as a kind of pain (lypē) or disturbance (tarachē) and pity as a kind of pain (2.5.1382 a 21 and 2.8.1385 b 13). In hisPoetics, however, pity and fear are associated with pleasure: ‘ The poet must provide the pleasure that comes from pity and fear by means of imitation’ (τ⋯ν ⋯π⋯ ⋯λέου κα⋯ ɸόβου δι⋯ μιμήσεως δεῖ ⋯δον⋯ν παρασκευάζειν14.1453 b 12–13). The question of the relationship between pleasure and pain in Aristotle's aesthetics has been studied primarily in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13.  27
    Tragédie, thumos, et plaisir esthétique.Elizabeth Belfiore - 2003 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 67 (4):451.
    Résumé — Dans cet article, je montre que l’une des fonctions de la tragédie est de procurer un entraînement au thumos , en l’habituant à devenir amical plutôt qu’agressif envers les philoi . Je donne d’abord un bref aperçu des thèses sur le thumos exposées dans les œuvres éthiques et politiques d’Aristote. Ensuite, j’étudie la relation entre le thumos et les actes de violence entre proches, qui constituent le sujet de la tragédie, en montrant comment la pitié et la crainte (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  91
    Aristotle’s Poetics. [REVIEW]Elizabeth Belfiore - 1995 - Ancient Philosophy 15 (1):268-272.
  15.  11
    Aristotle’s Poetics. [REVIEW]Elizabeth Belfiore - 1995 - Ancient Philosophy 15 (1):268-272.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  6
    Editors’ Introduction.Elizabeth S. Radcliffe & Mark G. Spencer - 2024 - Hume Studies 49 (1):7-8.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Editors’ IntroductionElizabeth S. Radcliffe and Mark G. SpencerThis issue opens with the winning essay in the Third Annual Hume Studies Essay Prize competition: “Hume beyond Theism and Atheism” by Dr. Ariel Peckel. Dr. Peckel’s essay was chosen as the winner from among papers submitted by emerging scholars from August 2022 through July 2023. Please see the full prize announcement with information about this talented Hume scholar elsewhere in this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  7
    The ethics of listening: creating space for sustainable dialogue.Elizabeth S. Parks - 2019 - Lanham: Lexington Books.
    The importance of ethical listening -- The power of difference and values that unite -- Take off your armor and bring down the walls: adopting a listening posture -- Dolls and cages: listening as investment and care -- Deep listening: remembering and responding with intentional focus -- Hyenas and chickens: listening as invitation -- Hope for sustainable hospitality -- References -- About the author.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  10
    Elizabeth S. Belfiore, Socrates’ Daimonic Art: Love for Wisdom in Four Platonic Dialogues , xvii + 304 pp., $99.00, ISBN 9781107007581. [REVIEW]Mary P. Nichols - 2013 - Polis 30 (2):354-356.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  7
    Elizabeth S. Belfiore, Socrates’ Daimonic Art: Love for Wisdom in Four Platonic Dialogues (Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 2012), xvii + 304 pp., $99.00, ISBN 9781107007581 (hbk). [REVIEW]Mary P. Nichols - 2013 - Polis 30 (2):354-356.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Hume's A Treatise of Human Nature: A Critical Guide.Elizabeth S. Radcliffe (ed.) - forthcoming - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  70
    Katharsis Elizabeth S. Belfiore: Tragic Pleasures: Aristotle on Plot and Emotion. Pp. xviii + 412. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992. £30. [REVIEW]Stephen Halliwell - 1993 - The Classical Review 43 (02):253-254.
  22. Alcali and acid, oil and vinegar : Hume on contrary passions.Elizabeth S. Radcliffe - 2017 - In Alix Cohen & Robert Stern (eds.), Thinking About the Emotions: A Philosophical History. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  68
    Principles of object perception.Elizabeth S. Spelke - 1990 - Cognitive Science 14 (1):29--56.
    Research on human infants has begun to shed light on early-developing processes for segmenting perceptual arrays into objects. Infants appear to perceive objects by analyzing three-dimensional surface arrangements and motions. Their perception does not accord with a general tendency to maximize figural goodness or to attend to nonaccidental geometric relations in visual arrays. Object perception does accord with principles governing the motions of material bodies: Infants divide perceptual arrays into units that move as connected wholes, that move separately from one (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   280 citations  
  24. Core knowledge.Elizabeth S. Spelke - 2000 - American Psychologist 55 (11):1233-1243.
    Complex cognitive skills such as reading and calculation and complex cognitive achievements such as formal science and mathematics may depend on a set of building block systems that emerge early in human ontogeny and phylogeny. These core knowledge systems show characteristic limits of domain and task specificity: Each serves to represent a particular class of entities for a particular set of purposes. By combining representations from these systems, however human cognition may achieve extraordinary flexibility. Studies of cognition in human infants (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   208 citations  
  25.  68
    Origins of knowledge.Elizabeth S. Spelke, Karen Breinlinger, Janet Macomber & Kristen Jacobson - 1992 - Psychological Review 99 (4):605-632.
    Experiments with young infants provide evidence for early-developing capacities to represent physical objects and to reason about object motion. Early physical reasoning accords with 2 constraints at the center of mature physical conceptions: continuity and solidity. It fails to accord with 2 constraints that may be peripheral to mature conceptions: gravity and inertia. These experiments suggest that cognition develops concurrently with perception and action and that development leads to the enrichment of conceptions around an unchanging core. The experiments challenge claims (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  26. Core knowledge.Elizabeth S. Spelke & Katherine D. Kinzler - 2007 - Developmental Science 10 (1):89-96.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   141 citations  
  27. Is women's labor a commodity?Elizabeth S. Anderson - 1990 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (1):71-92.
  28. Moral internalism and moral cognitivism in Hume’s metaethics.Elizabeth S. Radcliffe - 2006 - Synthese 152 (3):353 - 370.
    Most naturalists think that the belief/desire model from Hume is the best framework for making sense of motivation. As Smith has argued, given that the cognitive state (belief) and the conative state (desire) are separate on this model, if a moral judgment is cognitive, it could not also be motivating by itself. So, it looks as though Hume and Humeans cannot hold that moral judgments are states of belief (moral cognitivism) and internally motivating (moral internalism). My chief claim is that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  29. Object permanence in five-month-old infants.Elizabeth S. Spelke - 1985 - Cognition 20 (3):191-208.
    A new method was devised to test object permanence in young infants. Fivemonth-old infants were habituated to a screen that moved back and forth through a 180-degree arc, in the manner of a drawbridge. After infants reached habituation, a box was centered behind the screen. Infants were shown two test events: a possible event and an impossible event. In the possible event, the screen stopped when it reached the occluded box; in the impossible event, the screen moved through the space (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  30.  91
    The Democratic University: The Role of Justice in the Production of Knowledge*: ELIZABETH S. ANDERSON.Elizabeth S. Anderson - 1995 - Social Philosophy and Policy 12 (2):186-219.
    What is the proper role of politics in higher education? Many policies and reforms in the academy, from affirmative action and a multicultural curriculum to racial and sexual harassment codes and movements to change pedagogical styles, seek justice for oppressed groups in society. They understand justice to require a comprehensive equality of membership: individuals belonging to different groups should have equal access to educational opportunities; their interests and cultures should be taken equally seriously as worthy subjects of study, their persons (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  31. What makes us Smart? Core knowledge and natural language.Elizabeth S. Spelke - 2003 - In Dedre Getner & Susan Goldin-Meadow (eds.), Language in Mind: Advances in the Study of Language and Thought. MIT Press. pp. 277--311.
  32.  74
    Hume’s Psychology of the Passions: The Literature and Future Directions.Elizabeth S. Radcliffe - 2015 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 53 (4):565-605.
    in a recent article entitled “Hume on the Passions,” Stephen Buckle opens with the claim that Hume’s theory of the passions has largely been neglected. “Apart from a couple of famous sections in the Treatise concerning the sources of action,” he writes, “the subject matter has rarely excited interest.”1 His analysis of why the subject of the passions in Hume has been uninspiring points to the fact that readers have largely misunderstood the point of Hume’s theory. They usually regard the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33.  52
    Patterns of Moral Complexity.Elizabeth S. Anderson - 1990 - Philosophical Review 99 (3):472.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  34. The native language of social cognition.Elizabeth S. Spelke - unknown
    What leads humans to divide the social world into groups, preferring their own group and disfavoring others? Experiments with infants and young children suggest these tendencies are based on predispo- sitions that emerge early in life and depend, in part, on natural language. Young infants prefer to look at a person who previously spoke their native language. Older infants preferentially accept toys from native-language speakers, and preschool children preferentially select native-language speakers as friends. Variations in accent are sufficient to evoke (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  35. Hume on the Generation of Motives: Why Beliefs Alone Never Motivate.Elizabeth S. Radcliffe - 1999 - Hume Studies 25 (1-2):101-122.
    Hume’s thesis that reason alone does not motivate is taken as the ground for this theory: Reason produces beliefs only, and beliefs are mere representations of fact, which, without passions for the objects the beliefs concern, cannot move anyone at all. Discussions of the Humean theory of motivation usually begin with the motivating passions in place without asking about their genesis. This emphasis, I think, overlooks a good deal of what Hume’s thesis concerning the motivational impotence of reason is about: (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  36. John Stuart mill and experiments in living.Elizabeth S. Anderson - 1991 - Ethics 102 (1):4-26.
  37. aCCENT TrumpS raCE iN GuiDiNG ChilDrEN'S SOCial prEfErENCES.Elizabeth S. Spelke - unknown
    A series of experiments investigated the effect of speakers’ language, accent, and race on children’s social preferences. When presented with photographs and voice recordings of novel children, 5-year-old children chose to be friends with native speakers of their native language rather than foreign-language or foreign-accented speakers. These preferences were not exclusively due to the intelligibility of the speech, as children found the accented speech to be comprehensible, and did not make social distinctions between foreign-accented and foreign-language speakers. Finally, children chose (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  38.  84
    Language and number: a bilingual training study.Elizabeth S. Spelke - 2001 - Cognition 78 (1):45-88.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  39. Hume on Motivating Sentiments, the General Point of View, and the Inculcation of "Morality".Elizabeth S. Radcliffe - 1994 - Hume Studies 20 (1):37-58.
    That Hume 's theory can be interpreted in two widely divergent ways-as a version of sentimentalism and as an ideal observer theory-is symptomatic of a puzzle ensconced in Hume 's theory. How can the ground of morality be internal and motivating when an inference to the feelings of a spectator in "the general point of view" is typically necessary to get to genuine moral distinctions? This paper considers and rejects the suggestion that in moral education, for Hume, the inculcation of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  40. Sex Differences in Intrinsic Aptitude for Mathematics and Science?Elizabeth S. Spelke - unknown
    This article considers 3 claims that cognitive sex differ- ences account for the differential representation of men and women in high-level careers in mathematics and sci- ence: (a) males are more focused on objects from the beginning of life and therefore are predisposed to better learning about mechanical systems; (b) males have a pro- file of spatial and numerical abilities producing greater aptitude for mathematics; and (c) males are more variable in their cognitive abilities and therefore predominate at the upper (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  41. Conceptual precursors to language.Elizabeth S. Spelke & Susan J. Hespos - unknown
    Because human languages vary in sound and meaning, children must learn which distinctions their language uses. For speech perception, this learning is selective: initially infants are sensitive to most acoustic distinctions used in any language1–3, and this sensitivity reflects basic properties of the auditory system rather than mechanisms specific to language4–7; however, infants’ sensitivity to non-native sound distinctions declines over the course of the first year8. Here we ask whether a similar process governs learning of word meanings. We investigated the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  42.  65
    Love and benevolence in Hutcheson's and Hume's theories of the passions.Elizabeth S. Radcliffe - 2004 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12 (4):631 – 653.
  43.  69
    Reasons From The Humean Perspective.Elizabeth S. Radcliffe - 2012 - Philosophical Quarterly 62 (249):777-796.
    Humeans about practical reasoning have tried to explain how some of our desires are reason‐giving and some are not. On one account, we act from reasons only when we act on desires that cohere in a consistent set. On another account, we act on reasons only when we act on desires that do not undermine our values. Both accounts are problematic. First, the notion of a consistent set of desires is vague and introduces a criterion not necessarily rooted in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  44. Large number discrimination in 6-month-old infants.Fei Xu & Elizabeth S. Spelke - 2000 - Cognition 74 (1):1-11.
    Six-month-old infants discriminate between large sets of objects on the basis of numerosity when other extraneous variables are controlled, provided that the sets to be discriminated differ by a large ratio (8 vs. 16 but not 8 vs. 12). The capacities to represent approximate numerosity found in adult animals and humans evidently develop in human infants prior to language and symbolic counting.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   170 citations  
  45. Perceiving and reasoning about objects: Insights from infants.Elizabeth S. Spelke & Gretchen A. Van de Walle - 1993 - In Naomi Eilan, Rosaleen McCarthy & Bill Brewer (eds.), Spatial Representation: Problems in Philosophy and Psychology. Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  46. The Philosophical Works of Descartes.Elizabeth S. Haldane & G. R. T. Ross - 1914 - Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 11 (7):189-192.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  47. Hume on the Psychology of Public Persuasion.Elizabeth S. Radcliffe - 2023 - Cosmos + Taxis 12 (1+2):32-44.
    Political figures engage rhetoric and exalted speech to excite the imagination, stir up the emotions, and prompt their listeners to embrace and act on an ideological perspective. However, there is more to excellent public oratory than eloquence. Rational persuasion is also a key component, emphasizing facts, evidence, and reasoning. Hume acknowledges that rational persuasion alone is not terribly effective in the public arena. His corpus contains many references to eloquence. Dispassionate delivery of evidence does not have the psychological impact of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Natural number and natural geometry.Elizabeth S. Spelke - 2011 - In Stanislas Dehaene & Elizabeth Brannon (eds.), Space, Time and Number in the Brain. Oxford University Press. pp. 287--317.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  49.  41
    Core multiplication in childhood.Elizabeth S. Spelke - 2010 - Cognition 116 (2):204-216.
  50. Perception of unity, persistence, and identity: Thoughts on infants' conceptions of objects.Elizabeth S. Spelke - 1985 - In Jacques Mehler & R. Fox (eds.), Neonate Cognition: Beyond the Blooming Buzzing Confusion. Lawrence Erlbaum. pp. 89--113.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
1 — 50 / 999