Contents
17 found
Order:
Material to categorize
  1. Spinoza, Emanation, and Formal Causation.Stephen Zylstra - 2023 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 61 (4):603-625.
    Some recent scholars have argued that Spinoza's conception of causation should be understood in terms of the Aristotelian notion of a formal cause. I argue that while they are right to identify causation in Spinoza as a relation of entailment from an essence, they are mistaken about its philosophical pedigree. I examine three suggested lines of influence: (a) the late scholastic conception of emanation; (b) early modern philosophy of mathematics; and (c) Descartes's notion of the causa sui. In each case, (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. The First Draft of Spinoza's Ethics.Yitzhak Melamed - 2019 - In Jack Stetter & Charles Ramond (eds.), Spinoza in Twenty-First-Century American and French Philosophy: Metaphysics, Philosophy of Mind, Moral and Political Philosophy. London: Bloomsbury Academic. pp. 93-112.
    The two manuscripts of the Korte Verhanedling that were discovered in the mid-nineteenth century contain two appendices. These appendices are even more enigmatic than the KV itself, and it is the first appendix that is the subject of this study. Unfortunately, there are very few studies of this text, and its precise nature seems to be still in question after more than a century and a half of scholarship. It is commonly assumed that the appendices were written after the body (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Pascal versus Descartes on Solution of Geometrical Problems and the Sluse-Pascal Correspondence.Sébastien Maronne - 2010 - Early Science and Medicine 15 (4-5):537-566.
    In this article, I examine the respective role of equations and construction in geometrical problem solving according to Descartes and Pascal. I argue that whereas Descartes claims that an equation provides a solution to a geometrical problem even if it leads to an entangled construction, Pascal dismisses this claim and gives priority to construction. To this end, I deal with prototypical problems like Apollonius' problem of the three cir cles or Pappus' problem, both of which were tackled by Descartes and (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4. On Tait on Kant and Finitism.W. Sieg - 2016 - Journal of Philosophy 113 (5/6):274-285.
    In his “Kant and Finitism” Tait attempts to connect his analysis of finitist arithmetic with Kant’s perspective on arithmetic. The examination of this attempt is the basis for a distinctive view on the dramatic methodological shift from Kant to Dedekind and Hilbert. Dedekind’s 1888 essay “Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?” gives a logical analysis of arithmetic, whereas Hilbert’s 1899 book “Grundlagen der Geometrie” presents such an analysis of geometry or, as Hilbert puts it, of our spatial intuition. This (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. David Hilbert’s ’vorlesungen’ Logic and Foundations of Mathematics.Vito Michele Abrusci - 1989 - In G. Corsi, C. Mangione & M. Mugnai (eds.), Atti Del Convegno Internazionale di Storia Della Logica, San Gimignano, 1987. Editrice Cooperativa Libraria Universitaria Editrice, 1989. pp. 333-338..
  6. Husserl and Hilbert on completeness, still.Jairo Jose da Silva - 2016 - Synthese 193 (6):1925-1947.
    In the first year of the twentieth century, in Gottingen, Husserl delivered two talks dealing with a problem that proved central in his philosophical development, that of imaginary elements in mathematics. In order to solve this problem Husserl introduced a logical notion, called “definiteness”, and variants of it, that are somehow related, he claimed, to Hilbert’s notions of completeness. Many different interpretations of what precisely Husserl meant by this notion, and its relations with Hilbert’s ones, have been proposed, but no (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  7. Mathematics in Kant's Critical Philosophy: Reflections on Mathematical Practice.Lisa Shabel - 2002 - New York: Routledge.
    This book provides a reading of Kant's theory of the construction of mathematical concepts through a fully contextualised analysis. In this work the author argues that it is only through an understanding of the relevant eighteenth century mathematics textbooks, and the related mathematical practice, that the material and context necessary for a successful interpretation of Kant's philosophy can be provided.
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  8. From Kant to Hilbert, Volume 2: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics.William Bragg Ewald - 1996 - Oxford University Press UK.
    Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason is widely taken to be the starting point of the modern period of mathematics while David Hilbert was the last great mainstream mathematician to pursue important nineteenth cnetury ideas. This two-volume work provides an overview of this important era of mathematical research through a carefully chosen selection of articles. They provide an insight into the foundations of each of the main branches of mathematics--algebra, geometry, number theory, analysis, logic and set theory--with narratives to show (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9. Intuition and Reasoning in Geometry.Otto Hölder - 2013 - Philosophia Scientiae 17:15-52.
    The way in which geometrical knowledge has been obtained has always attracted the attention of philosophers. The fact that there is a science that concerns things outside our thinking and that proceeds inferentially appeared striking, and gave rise to specific theories of experience and space. Nonetheless, the geometrical method has not yet been sufficiently investigated. Philosophers who investigate the theory of knowledge discuss the question of whether geometry is an empirical science, but...
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10. Historical Mathematics in the French Eighteenth Century.Joan Richards - 2006 - Isis 97:700-713.
    At least since the seventeenth century, the strange combination of epistemological certainty and ontological power that characterizes mathematics has made it a major focus of philosophical, social, and cultural negotiation. In the eighteenth century, all of these factors were at play as mathematical thinkers struggled to assimilate and extend the analysis they had inherited from the seventeenth century. A combination of educational convictions and historical assumptions supported a humanistic mathematics essentially defined by its flexibility and breadth. This mathematics was an (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  11. The Distinctive Features of Seventeenth Century Geometry.F. Kokomoor - 1928 - Isis 10:367-415.
  12. Philosophy of Mathematics and Mathematical Practice in the Seventeenth Century by Paolo Mancosu. [REVIEW]Antoni Malet - 1997 - Isis 88:140-141.
  13. On the Mathematical Method and Correspondence with Exner.Bernard Bolzano (ed.) - 2004 - Rodopi.
    The Prague Philosopher Bernard Bolzano (1781-1848) has long been admired for his groundbreaking work in mathematics: his rigorous proofs of fundamental theorems in analysis, his construction of a continuous, nowhere-differentiable function, his investigations of the infinite, and his anticipations of Cantor's set theory. He made equally outstanding contributions in philosophy, most notably in logic and methodology. One of the greatest mathematician-philosophers since Leibniz, Bolzano is now widely recognised as a major figure of nineteenth-century philosophy. Praised by Husserl as "one of (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  14. The Philosophers of Gambling.N. Rescher - 1989 - Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 116:203-220.
    In An Intimate Relation: Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science Presented to Robert E. Butts on his 60th Birthday.
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Intuition and Reasoning in Geometry Inaugural Academic Lecture held on July 22, 1899. With supplements and notes: Otto Hölder (1859-1937). [REVIEW]Paola Cantu & Oliver Schlaudt - 2013 - Philosophia Scientiae 17 (1):15-52.
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Spiritual Presence and Dimensional Space beyond the Cosmos.Hylarie Kochiras - 2012 - Intellectual History Review 22 (1):41-68.
    This paper examines connections between concepts of space and extension on the one hand and immaterial spirits on the other, specifically the immanentist concept of spirits as present in rerum natura. Those holding an immanentist concept, such as Thomas Aquinas, typically understood spirits non-dimensionally as present by essence and power; and that concept was historically linked to holenmerism, the doctrine that the spirit is whole in every part. Yet as Aristotelian ideas about extension were challenged and an actual, infinite, dimensional (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17. Artifice and the natural world: Mathematics, logic, technology.James Franklin - 2006 - In K. Haakonssen (ed.), Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.
    If Tahiti suggested to theorists comfortably at home in Europe thoughts of noble savages without clothes, those who paid for and went on voyages there were in pursuit of a quite opposite human ideal. Cook's voyage to observe the transit of Venus in 1769 symbolises the eighteenth century's commitment to numbers and accuracy, and its willingness to spend a lot of public money on acquiring them. The state supported the organisation of quantitative researches, employing surveyors and collecting statistics to..
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations